A hypothesis about “ideal theory” and justice

by Chris Bertram on March 12, 2015

One of the most familiar and irritating moves in political philosophy is when a person says “oh, but my point was in ideal theory” as a response to some objection that references the grim and complicated real world. Not that I object in principle to ideal theory. But I do want to write this blog post to share a hypothesis about the ideal/non-ideal distinction and about why it has become more of a problem over time. The hypothesis is this: that in 1971 the gap between the ideal and the actual was a lot smaller than it is now. The world resembled Rawls’s ideal of the well-ordered society a lot more than it does now. Or at least, the North American bit of the world did.

Given that closer resemblance, people could do ideal theory without it looking like they were engaging in arcane hypotheses about a distant possible world. Political philosophy of the ideal variety looked a lot more relevant to what ought to happen.

Some people are probably going to think that this hypothesis is nuts, just because they think it obvious that the world has become better in all kinds of ways since 1971, so that we’re closer to the ideal now than we were then. In some respects that’s right. Things have improved for gay people, for women, and, in some limited respects, for non-white people. Those are not trivial changes. But I think the actual progress that there has been in those areas is very disappointing compared to the progress that we might reasonably have expected looking to the future from 1971, and that the value shifts that made that progress possible were already baked into liberal democratic societies by then, thanks to the sixties, thanks to the emergence of what used to be called the “new social movements” etc and that much of what has subsequently been achieved has been due to time, demography, persuasion, the dissemination of ideas from the enlightened few to the many, whilst the bigots gradually died off.

Meanwhile, things have gone radically wrong on the economic front and such progress towards racial equality as has been made, has yet been accompanied by the continued crimininalization, marginalization and brutalization of millions of poor black people in the US. Inequality is rampant, of course, but more than that, the conception of liberal democratic societies as functioning co-operative wholes in which each person might find their place and live a life of dignity in some occupation or other has been replaced by a highly individualized and fragmented view, where each person is held reponsible for their choices, and where those who fail deserve not the solidarity of their fellows but rather the resentment of the taxpayers who subsidize them. (This responsibilization of choice and hatred of subsidy is the defining motif of some of the views that get labelled “neoliberal”.)

The actual world resembles Rawls’s realistic utopia less in other ways too. In the Rawlsian vision, the co-operative whole – with each citizen finding their dignified role within – was set within an international system composed of similar co-operative schemes. Back in the 1970s, the actual world, or parts of it, resembled this somewhat. Now the elites and the corporations they manage no longer seem themselves as parts of such wholes. Perhaps they are domiciled in Monaco; perhaps the profits are in the Cayman Islands and cannot be repatriated for fear of the taxation they will incur. Meanwhile the real web of co-operation corresponds less and less to the national economy: whilst the boss is in Zurich, the factory is in China, and so on. The population on the territory too is more mobile, and the working assumption that nearly all those subject to the state will also be citizens, always a stretch, is more clearly false.

Still, the political philosophers do ideal theory. Some ideal theory is genuinely global or cosmopolitan, but a lot of it is about the parallel world of coexisting cooperative units inhabited by free and equal persons deriving self-respect from their place in the whole. In 1971-world, the co-operation wasn’t all that great, the people weren’t really free, or equal, and there was a lot of frustration and alienation. Even so, the liberal-democratic societies of 1971, when they squinted at themselves in the mirror, concealed a few blemishes, and got the lighting just right, could maybe persuade themselves that with a nip here and a tuck there, they could become the just societies of Rawlsian aspiration. So that kind of ideal theory, a theory of that society as it aspired to be, looked relevant to that very same society.

The non-ideal correlate of Rawlsian ideal theory isn’t coming back. Where to then?

{ 85 comments }

1

bianca steele 03.12.15 at 6:14 pm

How do people reconcile the fact that they’re only doing ideal theory? Some of them probably are more interested in studying it than in its applications. Do the others believe there’s a direct and obvious way to get from theory to practice? (I’m not trying to be snarky, it’s just that I’ve been pointed in that direction on occasion, and I can see the appeal and even some plausibility to thinking so, at least in theory.)

Last time you mentioned this, I did some googling and found some interesting articles (on ideal theory and race) which I haven’t read all of yet. But I’ve been pounding on the “empiricism” issue almost since I started commenting at CT because I’ve been assured, by very intelligent and erudite people with impeccable politics, of things that just aren’t so–but which match up extremely well with what you’d read in a certain kind of social theory (fifty years old though that theory might be). To say, for example, in 1985, that there’s no such thing as an independent entrepreneur, because in a modern economy planning is centralized in one way or another even in the US, viz. the big corporations like GM and IBM, is almost understandable. But only almost.

I mean, people can study what they like, and maybe I’ll learn something from it. I’d love to find some more left to add to my left-liberalism. But it doesn’t seem surprising to me that we don’t have much non-ideal theory.

2

js. 03.12.15 at 6:24 pm

a hypothesis about the ideal/non-ideal distinction and about why it has become more of a problem over time. The hypothesis is this: that in 1971 the gap between the ideal and the actual was a lot smaller than it is now. The world resembled Rawls’s ideal of the well-ordered society a lot more than it does now.

I totally buy this. I’m actually vaguely surprised by the idea that there would be serious opposition to this. I’m still a big fan of ideal theory. I’d have to think more to fully spell out why I think it’s important, but briefly: having a clear account of what ought to be is incredibly important, I think. (Which isn’t to deny that at least some people are attracted to ideal theory—myself very much inculded!—because it is in lots of ways a lot easier than non-ideal theory.)

3

js. 03.12.15 at 6:26 pm

I missed a “But” in my previous comment. Should be obvious enough where it goes, I think.

4

Foppe 03.12.15 at 6:53 pm

Yes and no. The main problem with that thesis is that, back in ’71, a lot more people were hidden from view/excluded from the count than there are now. (Whereas now, the major issue is that most of our interests are discounted — hurray..) Marital rape wasn’t even recognized yet; people of color’s voices were ignored with even more certainty and unselfconscious-ness than they are now; child abuse didn’t “exist” yet; there was more direct western control over the non-western world (though on a possible bright side, containerization didn’t exist yet, so the people living there were less ‘relevant’ as potential labor forces than they are now — but do read Saharan Journey).. As such, I’d say that if you stick to the west, around that time, it might be roughly excusable to argue that the theoryreality gap was smaller then than it was now (though then too, western actions had non-western consequences, and shipping volumes etc. were rising rapidly); that said, I have no idea why anyone’d want to engage in ideal theory…

5

Rich Puchalsky 03.12.15 at 6:56 pm

Maybe I don’t get this post because I’m not a political philosopher and because I was 7 years old in 1971. But if there was a change between a North American world close to ideal theory and a contemporary one in which ideal theory looks more and more utopian, didn’t that change happen substantially by 1981?

I was just casting around for the start of a poem about the strange Russians-buzzing-Dorset, we-must-counter-the-threat ideas that were just featured here. And really what immediately comes to mind is early-to-mid-80s Dead Kennedys songs. As far as I can tell, our societies haven’t learned anything politically since then.

6

Tom West 03.12.15 at 7:06 pm

As intimated in the article, the world can only be thought of as closer to Rawlsian theory in the past only if we ignore most of the world. I suspect that ideal theory has a much tougher time not because the world for middle-class white people has changed for the worse (although it likely has a bit), but the world that any theory is now expected to address is so much larger.

It’s infinitely harder to come up with theory and solutions that cover the massive complexities of cultural differences, governments, wealth levels and high levels of immigration. What’s a billion people raised out of poverty worth against the destruction of the middle class for millions? What’s the massive increase in welfare for tens of millions through wide-spread immigration worth against the increasing inability to enforce minimum standards of living for all?

It’s not that ideal theory has grown weaker, it’s that the challenges it is now expected to address (and have always been there lurking) have grown exponentially.

Anyway, that’s my fairly uninformed guess.

7

Tom West 03.12.15 at 7:08 pm

Have to compose faster – Foppe said it all more eloquently in #4.

8

L2P 03.12.15 at 7:08 pm

” The hypothesis is this: that in 1971 the gap between the ideal and the actual was a lot smaller than it is now. The world resembled Rawls’s ideal of the well-ordered society a lot more than it does now.”

I don’t think that’s true. Economically, yes. Distribution is less equal than in 1971. But culturally? Politically? In 1971 we didn’t seriously consider a Black president of the United States, or a woman. That was literally science fiction. We didn’t have to worry about the number of black or Asian or Hispanic faces on TV because that just wasn’t a thing. The number of women CEOs? Also not a thing. Stay-at-home-dads? Even in the 80’s that’s just for comedy. Can you imagine a fraternity being dissolved for singing a racist song in 1971?

That’s the problem with these “ideally” issues. In lots of ways the world IS closer to an ideal world, but in the one way that it really, really matters we are farther away.

9

Lisa Herzog 03.12.15 at 7:10 pm

Hi Chris, thanks for this interesting post. The broad outline seems right to me, and here is a suggestion for what follows: we need to focus much more on the institutions that actually hold power in this new globalized world. One of them are large organizations: business corporations, but also other kinds of organizations (think about the NSA…). We probably need both ideal and less ideal approaches to do so, and for thinking about economic questions from a normative perspective more broadly speaking. But we cannot pretend any more that the basic structures of nation states are going to take care of how the economy works….

10

Lisa Herzog 03.12.15 at 7:15 pm

PS: there is an asymmetry here between questions of economic justice and other questions of justice (regarding gender, race, minorities etc.). I agree with other commentators about the latter.

11

bianca steele 03.12.15 at 7:16 pm

Rich:

Well, it’s possible to pick up a number of VERY well-regarded books of popular economics from the 1960s–considered books of the left at the time and probably still now–and find the assumption, spelled out at length, that we have solved the problem of including everyone in society and getting them a decent, and decently paying, job–with the minor exception of a very small number of people who, by reason of racial discrimination or psychological alienation due to teeny-tiny faults in our culture, aren’t getting by–all of which problems are well understood and will soon be solved.

The New Left, feminism, new activism by blacks and other minorities (as other commenters have pointed out), all made it clear that things were a great deal worse (though they probably shared the assumption that we were mostly very close to solving the problems, for instance when Friedan points out that college educated mothers are having mental-health issues, she assumes this can be fixed by encouraging them to get jobs).

12

bianca steele 03.12.15 at 7:17 pm

Not to mention Vietnam, deindustrialization and globalization, and so on.

13

bob mcmanus 03.12.15 at 7:20 pm

Paragraphs 3 & 4 are for me connected via the Regulation School, at least for a start. It is forty years old, after all. But essentially the liberations of the 60s and 70s were about capital restructuring and rationalizing the workforce under declining profits. Not only did we need to get women into the labour market, we had to make them believe it was a liberation. Etc.

That is all. Sorry, let me think on it, maybe I can come up with a pithy quote.

Political economy is what is, and historical materialism attempts to show how what is came to be, and those are hard enough that what I have little time left for what will happen, how to make it so, and what it will look like. Anyway, nobody assigned me the tasks of coming up with the Plan or leading the troops.

“Ideal Theory” and Utopianism are dialectically connected to methodological and ideological individualism.

14

Mdc 03.12.15 at 7:47 pm

This seems right. Rawls was always pretty clear that his theory, oriented by “reflective equilibrium” and all, follows politics, not the other way around. That is, philosophers have to wait for real politics to actually happen in order to have something to theorize. And part of theorizing is always “ideal”- that is, accounting for the ideals implicit in real developments. This is one of the ways in which it’s fair to call Rawls a Kantiam.

15

Brett Bellmore 03.12.15 at 7:49 pm

” The hypothesis is this: that in 1971 the gap between the ideal and the actual was a lot smaller than it is now. The world resembled Rawls’s ideal of the well-ordered society a lot more than it does now.”

Are we assuming here that “the ideal” and “the Rawlsian ideal” are the same thing? Because I think there are certainly a lot of “ideals” out there, not just Rawls’.

16

Enzo Rossi 03.12.15 at 7:55 pm

Interesting. I’m not sure I buy the whole hypothesis, but it seems pretty clear that Western states in 1971 were a lot closer to the idealised “closed system” Rawls talks about. So if what makes the difference is globalisation, one could even try and leverage these historical considerations to build a slightly different argument for expanding the scope of justice.

17

Chris Bertram 03.12.15 at 8:04 pm

I don’t disagree with what people some of what people are saying re gender, race, minorities etc. and I hoped that was clear from the post

I’ve edited it to change

“we might have expected from 1971”

to

“we might reasonably have expected looking to the future from 1971”

Which was the thought I intended to convey.

18

Foppe 03.12.15 at 8:39 pm

“we might reasonably have expected looking to the future from 1971″ < Maybe; given that the first oil supply dispute was 2 years into the future, and the business roundtable was yet to be founded (but see the road to Mont Pelerin). But (admittedly with the partial benefit of hindsight) given the liberal aversion to acknowledging the political nature of, and taking a stance on issues of political economy, I’d say the writing was on the wall even then. Because so long as people keep allowing others to pretend as though “societies exist primarily to increase the output of things”, rather than that “the manufacture of goods is a subordinate moment in a larger process of fashioning people”, we’re just waiting for the other shoe to drop.

19

loneract 03.12.15 at 8:44 pm

Are there truly people who specialize in “ideal theory” and because of this are disconnected from the real world?

I hear about these types here and there, usually from folks announcing how different, how in touch with the poor and female and brown they and their studies are. But I have never actually met one in academia or elsewhere.

20

LFC 03.12.15 at 8:45 pm

from the OP:
The hypothesis is this: that in 1971 the gap between the ideal and the actual was a lot smaller than it is now. The world resembled Rawls’s ideal of the well-ordered society a lot more than it does now. Or at least, the North American bit of the world did.

I think the last sentence in the above passage is important: the hypothesis is mainly about the ‘developed’ world, esp., as I read the OP, the U.S., and with those restrictions (which make some sense in light of Rawls’s own focus) the proposition seems probably right (with the caveats about gender, race etc).

Expanded to the whole world, the picture is more mixed. E.g., child mortality rates are lower than in ’71, average life expectancies in a number of countries are probably longer, and the percentage of the global pop. living in extreme poverty has declined. Percentage of school-age children actually in school is prob. somewhat higher than in ’71. Not to say that any of these figures are now good — they aren’t — but there’s been some improvement. OTOH, ec. inequalities in many places are more marked, forms of labor exploitation (sweatshop, child labor, indentured servitude etc.) still exist on a large scale, many economies don’t generate enough decent jobs, the numbers living in slums and shantytowns in the ‘developing’ world have increased, etc.

b. mcmanus @13 may be right that the entrance of women into the workforce in large numbers in the developed world had to do w ‘rationalizing’ capitalism, but it did represent for some women a (subjectively experienced) liberation. (Which I suppose gets discounted by him under the heading of “individualism.”)

21

LFC 03.12.15 at 8:51 pm

Foppe @4 and T. West @6 made roughly similar points to mine (w some diff. in emphasis).

22

William Berry 03.12.15 at 9:03 pm

Very interesting post. I wish I had more time to comment rather than just rapidly skim posts and threads here to see what I can learn.

It occurs to me that the debate about “ideal theory” and “real world” considerations might be analogous to the debate we used to have back in the 1960s (and early 70s, when I was a university student) concerning “radicalism” and “meliorism”.

23

dsquared 03.12.15 at 9:21 pm

Me and Chris have had a discussion related to this (the extent to which Rawls can be seen as squarely in the tradition of Adam Smith) a few times, online and off. What I would say is that in many ways, the phenomenon he’s describing relates to a “loophole” in the ideal theory, and specifically in a problem of translating ideal theory into practice.

What I mean is that, if you were coming at Rawls from a very particular point of view, the thing you would find most attractive about the Difference Principle is that it gives you a straightforward formula for justifying any of your policies which don’t look too good for equality – they just have to crank out sufficient economic growth for you to be able to make a plausible-enough-for-government-work defence of them on Rawlsian grounds.

And, empirically, this is actually how most of these policies were justified. It’s somewhat complicated by the fact that, in terms of overall economic growth, the period 1971-2015 delivered much *less* growth than the preceding trente glorieuses (in the developed economies), but this point can successfully be dealt with by changing your benchmark and measuring yourself against the Communist societies rather than against your own recent track record. That would take you up to the mid 1990s, by which point you have China and India to point to as your success stories, as long as you’re prepared to pretend that China is a neoliberal success story which a surprising number of people are.

Like the Basel Capital rules, the problem is that people set up a standard without thinking that in many ways, the abuses of the rules are going to be more important than the actual rules. There’s probably room for a whole small sub-field of political theory dedicated to looking at ideal systems and seeing how they could be gamed.

24

Robespierre 03.12.15 at 9:40 pm

Couldn’t it be about momentum as well as actual current situation?
Things in the 60s were getting better quickly, both in terms of prosaic gdp and wage terms, and in terms of social progress.

25

roger nowosielski 03.12.15 at 10:07 pm

Chris may be right from the standpoint of Western political thought. The problem is, I find the Western perspective all too limited if our aim is to construct a viable political theory for the future. Have we all but forgotten the lessons of the postmodernists, Foucault, Lyotard, Agamben, Nancy? It is of course quite credible for some Western philosophers to ignore the continentals, but that’s certainly not true of all.

In any event, any credible political theory that aims to be global must posit the institution of the state as essentially coercive and counterproductive institution. And the same goes, of course, for the idea of a liberal, well-ordered society which, is propagated by the state, the post-industrial state, as some kind of an end the state has in mind. To think that is to indulge in fiction.

Unfortunately, it would seem that Christ cannot let go of John Rawls, the presumed champion of the liberal cause. Rather than trying to invent a new paradigm forging political philosophy in a new key, he seems to bemoan the passing of his idol.

A swan song.

26

Caleb 03.12.15 at 10:15 pm

The presupposition in the OP is that there are two approaches to political philosophy: one ideal in the sense of being removed from reality, the other non-ideal in the sense of being engaged with reality. But this is not how Rawls understood the distinction between ideal and non-ideal theory, and obviously if this were the distinction there would clearly be no point in thinking about ideal theory. Rather, Rawls proposed to *divide* political philosophy into two parts, ideal and non-ideal. The first part, ideal theory, seeks to discover what justice requires, and thereby to identify what counts as justice and injustice. The second part, non-ideal theory, seeks to understand how an unjust status quo can be transformed in the direction of justice. Understood in this way, ideal theory does not replace non-ideal theory but in fact serves it by (1) enabling non-ideal theory to identify what counts as an unjust status quo; and (2) identifying the target of transitional reforms. So at least as Rawls understood ideal theory, there is nothing about ideal theory as such that makes it irrelevant. (The specific content and scope of justice as fairness might be irrelevant in the sense of obsolete if there really is no longer anything of special significance about social cooperation within states, but that seems to be a different objection than the more general one that ‘ideal theory’ is irrelevant.)

27

LFC 03.12.15 at 11:02 pm

dsquared
if you were coming at Rawls from a very particular point of view, the thing you would find most attractive about the Difference Principle is that it gives you a straightforward formula for justifying any of your policies which don’t look too good for equality – they just have to crank out sufficient economic growth for you to be able to make a plausible-enough-for-government-work defence of them on Rawlsian grounds.

Well yeah that wd work if you ripped the DP out of its context and ignored the various other aspects of R’s theory that rule out inequalities that the DP, standing alone, might countenance.

28

Main Street Muse 03.12.15 at 11:04 pm

In 1971, we were three years past MLK, RFK assassinations and the Chicago Democratic convention (hardly an ideal political meeting by any stretch of the imagination!) Nixon was president – three years away from resigning in disgrace. 1971 was one year after Kent State shootings and a year before the Watergate burglary. 1971 was two years shy of the gas crisis that caused rationing in America (remember that?) 1971 was one year prior to the massacre of Israeli athletes at the Munich Olympics.

There is NO IDEAL WORLD. EVER. Trying to shove facts into “ideal models” never works. Never. And yet….

What bothered me most about run up to the 2008 crash was economists’ reliance on ideal theories to become blind to actual, real facts. “Housing prices have never declined, thus will never decline,” etc. and so on. We’ve also, in our devotion to the ideal models of that time, decided that no fraud happened at all – that that crash was just a big, unavoidable oops – that Repo 105 was a nice accounting tool, not a trick, that it’s okay for a bank to sell one client short as it goes long with another client ($GS an expert in this.)

From the OP: “The actual world resembles Rawls’s realistic utopia less in other ways too. In the Rawlsian vision, the co-operative whole – with each citizen finding their dignified role within – was set within an international system composed of similar co-operative schemes.”

Are you kidding me? How can you take that seriously? Please look at WalMart and the university system for how far we are removed from the Rawlsian ideal!!!

In ideal theory, facts do not matter – the theory’s the thing. Spare me the BS… deal with the real world instead. Where to now? Out of the clouds and onto earth…

29

Phil 03.12.15 at 11:11 pm

I wrote about my problems with Rawls here (and more generally here). I find in him an odd combination of the most rigorous abstraction and fairly hard-edged political realism – the parties in the original position aren’t bound for a world without money, for example, or even a world without capital (although I think Rawls does pronounce against excessive capital accumulation, or words to that effect). Perhaps this is approaching dsquared’s point from another angle – as if to say, “we never said there wouldn’t be a ‘worst off’…”.

Nothing to say about the OP except that I agree with it – and I wonder how much damage this historical situatedness is going to do to Rawls’s standing in the longer term. It’s already coming under challenge of sorts.

30

William Berry 03.12.15 at 11:12 pm

“Unfortunately, it would seem that Christ cannot let go of John Rawls . . .”

Well, maybe Rawls was Christ’s favorite ideal theorist. “Do unto others . . .”

One thing I love about CT: the commenters are so much smarter than the OPers.*

*Just kidding. Sorta.

31

js. 03.12.15 at 11:28 pm

Reading dsquared’s and Phil’s comments, it seems the problem is somewhat different from what I was originally thinking. I think it might be useful to distinguish ‘ideal theory’ in the specific Rawlsian sense from what might more generally be called ‘ideal theory’ in the history of political philosophy. In one sense, pretty much the entire history of political philosophy could be “ideal theory”—certainly The Republic, The Politics, the classical contract theorists are all prime candidates; so is, in a different way, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. But as dsquared and Phil both note, Rawls’ particular version of ideal theory raises raises quite distinct problems, and CB’s issue then is not with (what could be called) ideal theory in general, but with the Rawlsian view in particular. (This is all with a view to me getting the problem straight, so happy to be corrected.)

All that said, I am also very sympathetic to LFC’s point @24. There are several important equality-enhancing parts of Rawls’ view that are not the Difference Principle, not least Fair Equality of Opportunity.

32

ZM 03.12.15 at 11:34 pm

“Meanwhile the real web of co-operation corresponds less and less to the national economy: whilst the boss is in Zurich, the factory is in China, and so on. The population on the territory too is more mobile, and the working assumption that nearly all those subject to the state will also be citizens, always a stretch, is more clearly false.

The non-ideal correlate of Rawlsian ideal theory isn’t coming back. Where to then?”

Neil Brenner has done work re conceptualising the state and the urban to fit with changes from the 1960/70s.

I was just familiarising myself with his ideas a little yesterday and this morning since he is visiting to give a talk here next week, so I am not very well read. He seems to be influenced by Marx and the Frankfurt school, but given their periods of origin in competitive and Fordist/Keynesian capitalism asks of critical theory much like the OP asks of ideal theory:

“how the conditions of possibility for critical theory have changed today, in the early 21st century, in the context of an increasingly globalised, neoliberal used and financial used formation of capitalism”

I think one thing he is known for is in following others (eg Harvey) in looking at the urban as a process – he then sees the urban as no longer distinct or bounded by the form of the city – as the processes that form the material and society of contemporary cities take place on a planetary scale rather than a city or state scale.

If the problems the OP finds in ideal theory being able to meet the theoretical challenges of the present are that it is both 1. abstract; and, 2. only approximates a way of life in some terrains like the US which was a way of life in flux – then I am not sure how someone who likes ideal theory could fit it to the present – since if those are the problems it would have to change to be 1. less abstract ; 2. more applicable to a diverse but closely interrelated world.

If you changed both of these qualities then I am not sure it would still count as ideal theory, would it?

33

Sebastian H 03.13.15 at 12:15 am

“Like the Basel Capital rules, the problem is that people set up a standard without thinking that in many ways, the abuses of the rules are going to be more important than the actual rules.”

This is an excellent way at seeing the flaws in many semi-utopian modes of thought. Libertarianism is nice in that everyone gets to do whatever they want so long as they don’t hurt anyone else–BUT it turns out that quite a few people actually want to hurt each other, so we need to think about that. Communism is nice when people are willing to help each other out, but we need to be aware that lots of people prefer not to help each other out (either out of laziness, or meanness.)

If your ideal theory requires ideal humans, there is a problem.

34

LFC 03.13.15 at 1:30 am

Chris B. as an academic, as a political philosopher, probably — I’m sort of guessing — reads a fair number of the journals and finds in them a lot of articles whose ties to empirical reality are v. tenuous. They come across as operating in a sort of dream world. And these articles defend their approach by using the label ‘ideal theory’. And I completely get why Chris might find this annoying. If I had to read those articles, which I don’t, I think I might find it quite irritating also.

However, the extent to which this can fairly be ‘blamed’ on Rawls is, istm, an open question at best. R. has his weaknesses as presumably all philosophers do, but I’m not sure the ideal/non-ideal theory distinction is esp. one of them. Caleb @24 is, I think, roughly on the right track. R. assumes that people will comply w the principles of justice once they’ve been chosen: this ‘strict compliance’ is partly what he means by ‘ideal theory’. He says (TJ, 1st ed, p.246) that ideal theory “presents a conception of a just society that we are to achieve if we can.” If we can’t achieve it — because of “natural limitations and historical contingencies” — then we get, among other things, to the issue of which aspects of the ideal can be compromised and under what circumstances, and which can’t.

On these issues, as in some other instances, I don’t think R. was particularly well served by his expository style. Maybe he is clearer in Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (I don’t know b.c haven’t read it) but in TJ you have to read these passages more than once to see what he’s getting at, and even then it’s not always crystal clear. If the ideas were inherently so complicated that they couldn’t be simply and directly expressed, that’s one thing, but I have the sense that quite often he could have been somewhat more direct.

35

Tom Hurka 03.13.15 at 2:05 am

A Theory of Justice was published in 1971 but of course it was written, and its ideas were worked out, much earlier. I associate it much more with the spirit of the early ’60s, when many liberals were confident that some not-so-large changes — civil rights legislation, a more generous welfare system — could make large improvements in the quality, and equality, of American life. By 1971 it was clear that things weren’t going to be that simple. It’s not just the assassinations MSM mentions above, but the riots in Detroit, Newark, Memphis, etc., the failure of the War on Poverty to actually end poverty, issues about bussing, and much more. Look at the prominence in A Theory of Justice of the topic of civil disobedience — that’s a 1964-65 topic, not a 1971 topic, or at least in 1964-65 people could be much more optimistic about how much can be achieved by civil disobedience as against by more radical methods.

I’m not disagreeing with the OP, just suggesting that the time when good things “might have reasonably been expected looking to the future” was much more the mid-60s than 1971; by 1971 things were already bleaker.

I may have said this before, but I see A Theory of Justice as illustrating Hegel’s idea about the Owl of Minerva: Rawls was theorizing or systematizing a liberal vision whose heyday was already past, or which was already in decline in the realm of actual politics (as MSM said, Nixon was in the White House, Reagan not far away, etc.).

36

david 03.13.15 at 2:55 am

The ideal theory of the 1970s stems from the elitism of the 1950s, in the soaring aspirations of the postwar miracle. You can build a lot of interstates and new towns if you straightforwardly focus on the middle class and bulldoze the slums. And, indeed, a lot of interstates and new towns were built.

In the frame where government powers are expansive, and the voices of the inconvenient powerless negligible, then it makes sense to conceive of political solutions as predominantly easy but only blocked by the mendacity of (fellow elite) remnants of the old order. Suffering in Afro-Asia? Decolonization! Segregation in the South? Integration! The global threat of nuclear annihilation? Détente and mutual disarmament! Peace and prosperity are but a triumphant declaration obtained in unambiguous political mandate away. The world is awash in 1960s manifestos that seem to be making themselves felt.

And remember, crucially, through the late 1960s this seemed to be mostly borne out by events. Conversely, attempts to defy these trends – confrontation in Vietnam, populist gestures in defiance of integration, etc. – seemed both unmitigatedly evil and doomed to failure.

By the late 1970s this seems mostly reversed. The great post-colonial wave of civil wars in Africa was raging, whereas the unrepentant iron heel in East Asia had transformed from colonial poverty to taking-our-jobs. Integration had been met with white flight and the irreversible collapse of the New Deal tent. The achievements of détente had been met with overwhelming contempt by American voters. Second wave feminism met its equal in Phyllis Schlafly and the moral majority. It turns out that obtaining mandates requires more than empowerment and that obtaining policy requires more than declarations. Worst of all, of course, is that the decolonizers you’ve been cheering for hike up the price of oil, as they do.

Cue neoliberalism – and the exit of the the non-ideal correlated perspective.

37

John Quiggin 03.13.15 at 4:12 am

Last time we discussed this, I said that it struck me as strange to claim that the postwar US was anywhere close to satisfying the difference principle. It seemed (and seems) obvious that far more radically redistributive policies would be needed for this.

OTOH, it also seemed fairly clear that Rawls saw his arguments as being in line with a position only marginally left of (what was then the) centre – he wasn’t even keen on progressive taxation.

https://crookedtimber.org/2014/09/08/rawls-bentham-and-the-laffer-curve/

To restate my point from that post in a way a bit closer to what Chris is saying above, an ideal theory incorporates an (implicit or explicit) economic theory. Rawls, roughly speaking, reflected a strong view of the neoclassical-Keynesian synthesis, one in which demand management could ensure full employment, conditional on which minimally interventionist micro-economic policies and flat taxation rates would yield the best outcomes for everyone.

38

John Quiggin 03.13.15 at 5:45 am

@LFC “Well yeah that wd work if you ripped the DP out of its context and ignored the various other aspects of R’s theory that rule out inequalities that the DP, standing alone, might countenance.”

We had this dispute last time, I think, but it seems to me that things are the other way around.
1. The DP alone would call for far more radical redistribution than Rawls is prepared to countenance. No economist to the left of Arthur Laffer would deny this point (in fact, denying it is Laffer’s claim to fame).
2. The other aspects of the theory appear to allow for more inequalities, not to rule them out. I haven’t seen this spelt out, but whenever I make point 1, it’s suggested that I shouldn’t be emphasising the DP so much.

39

Ze Kraggash 03.13.15 at 7:23 am

Liberalism (or ‘neo-liberalism’, if you wish) has failed.

Russia was a perfect experiment: oligarchy controlling (fair&square) the state for ~10 years, leading to a complete, total collapse. And then a quick change, a new government, completely removing the oligarchs from politics and from any significant media ownership. And this new government – not particularly competent or energetic, and only mildly nationalistic – achieved amazing, incredible results, by any measurement. I saw somewhere that the average salary increased, between 2000 and 2010, 7-fold, in dollar terms. That’s 700%. Every welfare-related statistic has improved by leaps and bounds.

So that’s that, that’s the future. Of course the neo-liberal oligarchy everywhere is furious; of course they won’t go without a fight. It’ll be fun to watch.

40

Chris Bertram 03.13.15 at 8:00 am

A few brief reactions to people:

Caleb: sure, I understand that. But in my judgement the ideal theory of TJ bears the mark of the society it was composed in rather clearly, and from the perspective of that society as reimagined in TJ, the transitional task of non-ideal theory looks rather less daunting that it does today.

Tom Hurka: Ha! There’s an essay by Brian Barry that also uses the Owl of Minerva line re Rawls. Yes, I think you are absolutely right about the timescale, and I should have shifted the claim earlier than 1971.

41

Bruce Baugh 03.13.15 at 8:07 am

I’d describe the early ’70s situation as better than the present in terms of vectors and expectations. There were a lot of problems, and very much a still-evolving of how many and widespread they were. But there were also a lot of working- and middle-class white people on board with the idea that those problems could and should be addressed, and that more and more people could come inside the expanding circle of reliable opportunity and fairness. The big loss, as I see it, is that expectation. The right wing’s done a fabulous job of persuading a solid majority of the voting white population that they don’t actually deserve any of that stuff, and also that their losing it is all the fault of these others they were trying to help, and that the well-being of those who’ve actually been ripping them off is what really counts.

1971 felt to a lot of its inhabitants like it was heading some place that a lot of people in 2015 think is simultaneously impossible and undesirable.

42

dsquared 03.13.15 at 8:21 am

Redistributive justice ended in 1973
Between the end of “The Wicker Man” and the first Springsteen LP

43

John Quiggin 03.13.15 at 9:00 am

The War on Poverty wasn’t lost: the government switched sides.

44

reason 03.13.15 at 9:32 am

Thinks have improved for gay people, for women, and, in some limited respects, for non-white people.”

I find kind of cute, and it isn’t exactly wrong, but is it what you meant to say?

[Thanks. Fixed. CB]

45

Maya 03.13.15 at 10:46 am

I certainly see the force of Chris B’s hypothesis. The relationship between the Rawlsian society and the existing society in time of the book’s writing can be described as one of optimistic reconstruction or hopeful expectation for the future. …with a geographical qualification: this was a reality that existed in a small number of relatively wealthy and powerful states, and that coexisted with plenty of warfare in a very violent and militarized international context. In the 1990s, the Zeitgeist in political theory, liberal and left-leaning, was to overcome these dark sides of the Cold War era by overcoming state sovereignty and going global. I think this was a mistake, and thought the same in the 1990s. Rawls opposed this trend in The Law of Peoples seen by many as a grave disappointment. Political theorists and IR scholars obviously did not bring about the current gruesome disparities between economic, social and political powers. But they contributed their fair share to teaching students and sometimes the public beyond to affirm and endorse the transformation that brought this about: Love global civil society and dispersed sovereignty! Who needs the state, anyhow?? Maybe it is time to bring states back in the theory and understand the ways they are indispensable for late transnational capitalism (or however the economic system of today is to be called) and where they are capable of taking action to change devastating economic trends. It will still be a huge challenge to influence decision makers to take such actions, but academia can help figure out where to concentrate the efforts.

46

Main Street Muse 03.13.15 at 11:02 am

JQ @37 “…an ideal theory incorporates an (implicit or explicit) economic theory. Rawls, roughly speaking, reflected a strong view of the neoclassical-Keynesian synthesis, one in which demand management could ensure full employment, conditional on which minimally interventionist micro-economic policies and flat taxation rates would yield the best outcomes for everyone.”

I am not an ecumenist and have not read Rawls – you seem to indicate that Rawls feels businesses can solve the social problems of a nation (demand management leading to full employment, with minimally interventionist policies, etc. Or perhaps you mean demand management as dictated by government?) What would people get paid if there were no minimum wage (a policy which some politicians feel is outrageously interventionist)?

Don’t really know what you mean by “war on poverty was not lost; the government switched sides.” The war on poverty was lost. Horribly lost. Neither government nor businesses are interested in solving the issues of poverty. Just come to NC and I’ll show you what I mean.

Bruce Baugh @41 “but there were also a lot of working- and middle-class white people on board with the idea that those problems could and should be addressed…”

HOW did these people feel these problems should be addressed? Via a business solution (which we’ve seen is in the US as being determined by how to maximize profit and minimize costs of labor – hard to have a consumer-driven economy when consumers wages never grow.)

People looked to government – not business – to solve problems. Since Reagan, that approach has been battered and bashed relentlessly by the party of the wing nuts. We’re at a place now where government is paralyzed and held hostage by the loony fringe of the GOP (#47traitors as an example.) How does ideal theory address that inconvenient fact?

47

bjk 03.13.15 at 12:44 pm

The OP goes out of his way to not use “nation-state”:

“the co-operative whole . . . within an international system composed of similar co-operative schemes . . . such wholes . . . corresponds less and less to the national economy . . . The population on the territory too is more mobile . . . all those subject to the state will also be citizens, always a stretch, is more clearly false.”

So basically the OP is nostalgic for the nation-state. So why doesn’t the OP come right out and say, hey, the nation state is the only way to protect the interests of workers against global capital? That would seem like the obvious response. “Where to then?” How about back to the nation-state?

48

LFC 03.13.15 at 1:29 pm

JQ @38

We probably did have the same dispute about the DP last time. Maybe I’ll backchannel you on this point sometime as 1)don’t have a lot of time today and 2)not sure the details of the dispute are of wide interest.

49

engels 03.13.15 at 1:35 pm

It sounds like we need a John Rawls for 2015: someone who can abstract from the US liberal politics of the 2000s and produce an authoritative work of high-minded idealism which can be translated into 30 languages and taught to young people all over Europe and the developing world. (If we have to cut out some other stuff out to make space for that, oh well…)

50

Anarcissie 03.13.15 at 1:47 pm

I am shocked to hear that, in 1971, the real world as I experienced in then was close to any sort of ideal. I remember it as a period when, it was clear, the ruling class consensus on the care and management of the Bismarckian Welfare state had fallen apart because of its seemingly incurable failures, a sort of low-level civil war was smouldering along in the streets, with a large component of individualistic crime, and an insane tide of imperial ambition was just beginning to break in Indochina. It is true that politically and economically, things were going to get worse for a lot of people (not me), but the ways in which they were going to get worse were already implicit in 1971.

I am not a student of Rawls, but I do think it is pretty clever to propose a fantasy of a inchoately communistic society which then chooses to transform itself into — surprise! — modern capitalism with Welfarist patches. But what function do such fantasies serve in the so-called real world?

51

areanimator 03.13.15 at 2:25 pm

Failure and impending collapse of the welfare state, a breakdown of grand imperial ambitions, low-level civil war in the streets… The ’70s don’t seem that different from today, really.

52

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 2:26 pm

This was also happening in or around 1971. But if the grown-ups around me had abandoned liberalism for something else before well into the 1980s, they were keeping the fact well hidden.

It seems to me “ideal theory” is, in some respects, just another word for Platonism: ideas and all are right there in the mind of God waiting for us to discover them, as opposed to Aristotelian discovery through science. There’s a pretense of its being “scientific” just as in the Middle Ages there was a pretense that the Aristotelian tradition led up to an ossified set of concepts as rigid as any Randroid’s. (Later you got Hume, Kant, Hegel, Marx, which recapitulated the whole thing in a more confusing way; then even later you got structuralism and poststructuralism, though as far as I can tell nobody can tell which side of the Plato-Aristotle divide either of those is even on.) Why do you need non-ideal theory, then, when it’s all there?

And so practical debates are limited to a increasingly narrow range of questions within increasingly abstruse economic theory.

53

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 2:29 pm

Sorry, this.

54

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 2:30 pm

55

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 2:32 pm

2 Journal of Law & Education 1973 Limited Right to Strike Laws – Can They Work When Applied to Public Education, The

http://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/jle2&div=53&id=&page=

56

david 03.13.15 at 2:51 pm

What’s with the sudden tide of reactionary nationalists? Did CT get linked on a ethnonationalist blog somewhere?

57

Chris Bertram 03.13.15 at 3:04 pm

“So basically the OP is nostalgic for the nation-state. ”

Nope, not one bit. Roughly, and accepting your “nation state” framing, the OP wants us to develop a cosmopolitan political philosophy that corresponds to the cosmopolitan world we live in rather than producing more stuff about the idealized counterparts of vanished nation states.

58

Aaron Lercher 03.13.15 at 3:24 pm

“[I]n 1971 the gap between the ideal and the actual was a lot smaller than it is now.”
This hypothesis sounds different, depending on how the “gap” and “actual” are understood.
Rawls’s TJ presents a method of argument in politics, and the ideal theory is part of how Rawls thinks we need to argue on behalf of justice. Rawls in TJ seems to have considered the ideal theory to be a lot closer to politically effective rhetoric in the US than we can today. In the US back in 1971, conscientious objection, civil disobedience, and economic redistribution were legitimate forms of political rhetoric for clearly identified political aims. Rawls justifies these forms of argument. Today in the US, the rhetoric of the Occupy movement was entirely ideal and not closely connected with political aims. That’s one way to understand the “gap” between ideal and actual.
Is this because the gap between real US society and ideal justice was “smaller”? Maybe. But this applies a quantitative metaphor that is foreign to parts of Rawls’s theory (especially priority of liberty and dignity of individuals). So we’re not going to measure the “gap” between reality and theory, if Rawls’s theory is our theory of justice. (Unless we try to turn the difference principle into the main part of the theory. Then maybe we can use an index of income inequality as a measure.)
But maybe the “gap” can be measured in another way.

59

engels 03.13.15 at 3:32 pm

the OP wants us to develop a cosmopolitan political philosophy that corresponds to the cosmopolitan world we live

Enjoy it while it lasts

60

Chris Bertram 03.13.15 at 3:51 pm

@engels: well that is to assume that King Cnut’s impending electoral triumph will have the sea-repelling effects promised in his manifesto.

61

david 03.13.15 at 3:53 pm

The liberal owl of Minerva flies at neoliberal dusk, and the ghost of Brad Delong points and laugh as we all vote Blue Labour?

62

david 03.13.15 at 4:12 pm

Oh, I am slow. But compared to the 2011 tiff with Delong, today the ethnic immigration question seems harder and harder to frame appropriate left-wing and populist solutions around. The only people who really seem to believe in a global wealthy conspiracy against the masses – who behave as one would behave if there [i]were[/i] such a conspiracy – are crazy neofascist racists. So one is left with unconvincing rhetoric, a populism of tofu rather than red meat. Not really a recipe for success.

But we’ve actually been here before, haven’t we, at least for Commonwealth citizens – the Commonwealth nonwhite immigration question of the 1960s. The UK Labour Party in that period, sufficiently humiliated by electoral losses, decided that office was well worth compromising on anti-nationalist and anti-racist principles and scrubbed defending free Commonwealth movement from its ambitions. Is contemporary New Labour – neoliberalised social democracy and all its knotting of states around nebulously popular commitments like refugee rights – capable of shutting out baser populism? We’ll see.

63

Bruce Wilder 03.13.15 at 4:23 pm

david: The only people who really seem to believe in a global wealthy conspiracy against the masses . . . .

It seems to me the wealthy conspirators believe. So there is that.

64

LFC 03.13.15 at 4:31 pm

Chris Bertram:
the OP wants us to develop a cosmopolitan political philosophy that corresponds to the cosmopolitan world we live in

As Chris B. knows, not long after A Theory of Justice was published some readers began criticizing Rawls for having ignored the global dimension of inequality and having limited his focus to national societies. Beitz’s work along these lines was published in article form a few years after TJ came out, and then in book form in 1979 as Political Theory and International Relations. Henry Shue’s Basic Rights followed a couple of years later. Pogge in Realizing Rawls discussed how R.’s theory could be extended to be global in scope. They didn’t all the say the same thing, but they were all dissatisfied with R’s lack of cosmopolitanism and inattention to inequalities, whether within-country or between-country, that were at least partly a result of global political-economic forces. Now, decades later, there is so much writing on global justice that one person would probably have difficulty keeping up w/ it all (I make little or no effort to do so).

Without TJ and its shortcoming in this respect as a prod, would this huge amount of work on global justice have happened? Probably eventually, but probably not as quickly as it did. So maybe we should give a little credit to Rawls for having, albeit largely inadvertently, helped spark that, instead of, per engels upthread, smugly dumping on R. as “high-minded idealism” that simply abstracted from postwar U.S. liberalism. Even if it was partly that, it proved generative (to use a fashionable word I don’t really like but which seems apt here).

And btw, contra Tom Hurka above, civil disobedience was not just “a 1964-65 topic” but also a ‘hot topic’ into the early 1970s (anti-Vietnam-war movement).

65

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 4:58 pm

Even if it was partly that, it proved generative (to use a fashionable word I don’t really like but which seems apt here).

Yes, (ISTM) it does.

And btw, contra Tom Hurka above, civil disobedience was not just “a 1964-65 topic” but also a ‘hot topic’ into the early 1970s (anti-Vietnam-war movement).

And well beyond that (though it worked best, apparently, with laws preventing people from being in a certain place–Jim Crow–or compelling them to be in a certain place–the draft–and less well when it became a matter of trying to get arrested for violating one law in order to protest something else).

And on the other hand, even in the 1960s: if you read occasional pieces by academics who were admired by the new movements, in some cases, you can see the point at which they recoil and tell their students they have it all wrong (and, maybe not coincidentally, where they start working hard to pull their theories back into the realm of the pure ideal).

66

david 03.13.15 at 5:03 pm

I think the point was not to bash Rawls in particular but to point out an interesting aspect of the kind of perspective that Rawls seemed to be speaking towards, viz., a world where all one had to do as a liberal member of the elite in good standing was to sufficiently exhort conservative members of the elite toward consistency in broadly shared ideals, and the gears of managerial government would obediently turn and immanentize the mandate. Rawls doesn’t seem to worry about a collapse in the legitimacy of ambitious federal mandates, unexpectedly crippling difficulties in realizing those mandates, or the disappearance of a consensus in said ideals. But you don’t have to invoke Rawls in the particular to motivate this observation. Who was Galbraith speaking to? Why does the Port Huron Statement demand that the Democrats expel the Dixiecrats without bothering to perform a quick demographic calculation, as if it’s obviously the case that the party of Lincoln would stand hand-in-hand with integrationist progressives against them?

It’s valid, I think, as an observation. I do want to point out that the gears eventually turned again to anoint a new elite perspective, one with less Anglo-American political philosophy and more Anglo-American economics. Likewise, again: broadly shared ideals, assuming that measures to tamp down politics would actually tamp down politics, etc. In terms of sketching abstract theoretical claims and having Serious People take these Seriously, both on the New Labour/DLC/etc left and gleeful right, it’s a good time to be an economist – I think that much is true, without making any commitments to the truthfulness or falsity of the claims that economists or philosophers make. It’s not the same kind of ideal theory, but it’s idealized theory nonetheless. We just take different things for granted.

67

David 03.13.15 at 6:17 pm

(Not the David of 66)
I’m sure Chris is right in his basic contention, but I actually think Rawls is more a representative case than anything else. Most people (including me in 1971) thought along similar lines.
Consider: at that date, we had had twenty-five years of economic growth and full employment, but also unheard of progress in health, education, social security, transport, infrastructure and massive redistribution of income. (I accept this might have been less true in the US). The European empires were effectively over or just ending, progress was bing made in European integration … and so on. What is remarkable is that this had all been done, if not quite according to Rawlsian formulae, then at least without violence, or serious social conflict after the late 1940s. It really did seem as if the ruling class of the day, chastened by WWII and worried about the electoral appeal of Communism, had bitten the bullet and decided that reform was ultimately in their best interest. It seemed reasonable (and I think it was) to expect continued progress towards, say, a thirty hour working week, lifetime education, planetary exploration and all the other things we used to dream of. Obviously the world wasn’t perfect, and only an idiot would suggest it was, but the key is that it was visibly getting better, just as now it is visibly getting worse.
But of course it was all based on an assumption, which was that the ruling class would continue to play along. It didn’t, and the whole 1945-75 economic order was overturned in a few years, behind the facades of inflation and the oil crisis, with almost no serious opposition from the Left. Indeed, in a tacit bargain, the organized Left didn’t seriously oppose the lurch towards neoliberalism (from which many of its leaders benefitted personally, and still do) and turned to identity politics instead . Having despaired of increasing the size of the cake, or even its economic distribution, they were then free to fight each other over which identity groups gained, and which lost.
In other words, the world implicit in Rawls’s views was essentially an optical illusion, a facade which could be and was torn down when it became tedious to continue it.

68

david 03.13.15 at 6:19 pm

(the david of 66, not 67)

That timing seems wrong – the New Left and the embrace of countercultural identity politics far predates the oil crisis.

69

Tom Hurka 03.13.15 at 6:51 pm

What I thought was 1964-65 about Rawls’s treatment of civil disobedience was the assumption that that was all that was needed, that no more radical tactics need be contemplated. And Rawls’s treatment of the topic was very high-minded. His idea was that the civil disobedient thinks his society is generally just but is failing to live up to its own ideals in a particular area; his disobedience is aimed at getting people to think more about what they already believe and see what it entails. I don’t think the Vietnam War protesters of 1971 thought that. But it expresses the kind of liberal optimism I take to be characteristic of the earlier 60s.

And re JQ: what I would say about the War on Poverty was that the earlier assumption was that poverty could be eliminated or at least greatly reduced with not much effort and at not too great a cost. When the task proved harder and more expensive, many former supporters backed off. That’s not just the government changing sides. It’s people changing sides when their assumptions about what the game was turned out to be false. That’s just another example of the optimism of early 60s liberalism being confronted with a rougher, more difficult world.

70

roger nowosielski 03.13.15 at 7:05 pm

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 2:26 pm, #52

I have no idea who are the grown-up you’re referring to. You can’t be taking about the man in the street, because the man in the street doesn’t give a hoot about such labels. And you certainly can’t mean the leaders of the Civil Rights movement, because “liberalism” wasn’t what it was about. So I must assume that you must mean white intellectuals, whether academics or not, for only white intellectuals would have a stake at keeping such a fiction alive (see Anarcissie’s comment immediately prior to yours).
To keep the record straight, the counter-culture movement also wasn’t about liberalism; it was a critique of American/Western values and it transcended such political/[philosophical) categories. As to the situation on the campuses at the time, it seems you have also missed the boat. All throughout my undergraduate years in the late sixties and postgraduate studies at NYU in the early seventies, a liberal society was precisely what was being critiqued, both by the students and most of the faculty. The atmosphere at NYU and the New School was one of extreme radicalism, devoted to the writings of the German and French schools of thought. And, need I add, some writings of Foucault were already available in English. Foucault may not have coined the term “Project Enlightenment” (Lyotard perhaps), but all the seeds of the pertinent critique of Western liberal values were certainly present in his work.
My guess would be that liberalism had (again) come into vogue in the late seventies and early eighties, to provide a sort of banner and a rallying cry to the disgruntled and powerless white intellectual, to provide him or her with their raison d’être – certainly not anything to get excited about. And Rawls’s idea of a well-order society fits this bill to a T.

71

roger nowosielski 03.13.15 at 7:08 pm

the above post refers to the following citation:

“. . . if the grown-ups around me had abandoned liberalism for something else before well into the 1980s, they were keeping the fact well hidden.”

72

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 7:23 pm

roger,

I’m sorry, you’re complaining that the grade school or high school student in the 1970s and early 1980s who read newspapers would never have heard the world “liberalism” or met someone who called themselves a “liberal”?

And you’re saying that because at NYU and the New School there was a great deal of radicalism in the late 1970s, there must not have been reaction, then or earlier, in other places? (I can sympathize, having taken classes at Harvard after graduating from Columbia, it took me a while to figure out that when it was said that someone didn’t get tenure because they were too far left, it didn’t mean they were actually a Communist.) You’ve never heard the saying about after 1970 or so, all options for political action and radicalism dried up, so everyone had to move to the right or hide their beliefs to survive? Forgive me for not drawing the vast conclusions you obviously want me to draw from your personal experience.

And you’re saying that we have to use your definition of “liberalism”? And I have to have my memories vetted for terminological and ideological correctness, not only by scholars of history who know the established version, but by every individual person on the Internet who thinks they know what’s correct?

73

roger nowosielski 03.13.15 at 8:09 pm

I’m not certain where you’re going with this, Bianca. First off, I wasn’t talking of grade- or high school students, so perhaps we’re experiencing, shall I say? a generation gap. Secondly, I didn’t mean to suggest that the academic environment at NYU or the New School was in any way unique; quite the contrary, I believe it was more or less prevalent throughout most of the America’s campuses. I may agree with you in that the options for a viable political options have more or less “dried up” during or after the seventies – which is precisely why, I argue, liberalism had come to represent what remained, the only political philosophy that could be embraced by the disgruntled intellectual. But having said all that, I fail to detect any considerable points of disagreement between us. Except perhaps …

Yes, “my definition of liberalism.” Well, I view it, especially in this day and age, as an ideology. Do you not?

74

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 8:28 pm

Roger,

I think you’re being disingenuous. It’s very kind of you to note that we probably don’t disagree, but you needn’t have bothered.

You asked me who the grown-ups in question were, whom I mentioned. So those were the people we were talking about. Now it seems that you’re complaining that you weren’t talking about the people whom I mentioned. Whom you asked about. I wouldn’t call this a generation gap, exactly.

75

LFC 03.13.15 at 8:48 pm

Tom Hurka @69

What I thought was 1964-65 about Rawls’s treatment of civil disobedience was the assumption that that was all that was needed, that no more radical tactics need be contemplated. And Rawls’s treatment of the topic was very high-minded. His idea was that the civil disobedient thinks his society is generally just but is failing to live up to its own ideals in a particular area; his disobedience is aimed at getting people to think more about what they already believe and see what it entails. I don’t think the Vietnam War protesters of 1971 thought that. But it expresses the kind of liberal optimism I take to be characteristic of the earlier 60s.

Ok, fair enough. I guess the discussion of civil disobedience is not a part of TJ that I paid close attention to, either when I first encountered the book or later, so I’d have to go back and look at it again to engage further on this specifically.

I would note btw — not that it’s directly relevant to the above but as a matter of interest — that in 1968 Rawls gave a talk to students in which he said that in his view resistance to the Vietnam War was justified. (Presumably he meant non-violent resistance.) The talk is discussed is briefly in the post I’m about to link, which was written by a history grad student at U. of Wisconsin who is writing his dissertation on Rawls. (Link in next box.)

76

LFC 03.13.15 at 9:01 pm

http://s-usih.org/2014/07/roundtable-u-s-foreign-policy-and-the-left-chapter-6.html

An excerpt:

In 1968 Rawls spoke to students at Harvard about his sentiments on the [Vietnam] conflict. … Rawls detailed the reasons why the young listeners standing before him had a right to resist the draft. They boiled down to the fact that the war itself was unjust and that [its] claims otherwise were wrong. Rawls recited two grounds for this charge: first, there was no just cause for the U.S.’s initiated entry into Vietnam; and second, that “our armed forces engage in actions which violate the limits on the appropriate means of waging war.” Rawls coupled these grounds with historical facts he deemed essential to evaluating the situation. … Rhetoric casting the war as just—as a defense of democracy against the expansion of communism—was simply morally illegitimate…. Thus students not only had a right to resist service in Vietnam; it was their duty to do so. [5]

This doesn’t in itself show much more than that Rawls opposed the war on grounds that by 1968 a lot of (though not all) liberals agreed on. But that he spoke out in this way at an anti-war rally in the company of, among others, “his friend and former MIT colleague Noam Chomsky” (as the post’s author puts it) is, I think, worth noting.

77

roger nowosielski 03.13.15 at 9:04 pm

Disingenuous I certainly am not, Bianca. I am not really complaining ’bout who were the so-called “grown-ups” you were talking about. But now since the truth is out, and I had suspected all along you were talking about an earlier generation (are you not now?). the point of my post was simply that these people, grade and/or high-school students, don’t really matter. Why not?

Since they’re being spoon-fed all along, and that real thinking, for most of us at least, the kind of thinking we do for ourselves, only starts once we enroll in a college? I’m not speaking of geniuses, of course, and I am the least person to qualify.

So how am I being disingenuous, do tell!

78

bianca steele 03.13.15 at 9:23 pm

Roger,

The generous, charitable, courteous thing to do here would be to point out that you seem to have misread @52. It occurred in a discussion of when certain changes had taken place. I said already in this thread, and other times in comments here at CT, that I was in college in 1985. So who “grown-ups . . . well into the 1980s” might be — it really doesn’t seem difficult. All that about an earlier generation? I don’t follow you.

I’m having a hard time finding something to say to you here that isn’t snarky or insulting. There’s really nothing in anything you’ve written that has anything to do with my comments, except that you started off with “bianca, you,” so I really don’t think there’s anything to say.

79

harry b 03.13.15 at 9:54 pm

Well, it was reasonable in the mid-60s and even in 71, given the evidence, to think that things were moving and would continue to move in the right direction. Things have been moving in the wrong direction since the mid 70s, and although Rich is right that by 1981 decisive measures had been taken they have continued to move in the wrong direction. I think CB’s hypothesis is reasonable. But I also think that doing non-ideal work is just really, really hard, and not even something we have been well trained for, and that, too might play an explanatory role.

80

roger nowosielski 03.13.15 at 10:09 pm

@78

Sorry, Bianca, but I didn’t realize I was supposed to keep tabs on you, as to when you had gone to college, when you graduated, etc. I didn’t exactly follow your career on CT either, as I don’t with any of the other commenters. I just try to respond as best I can to what I see in front of me. And if being snarky or insulting is the best you can muster at this point, then indeed it is for the better that we call it quits.

81

MPAVictoria 03.13.15 at 11:10 pm

I think Chris has a point. One of the things that drives me nuts about the current political climate is that we are currently richer than we have ever been as a society and yet we are constantly told that we cannot afford the things which we used to have. Well funded universal healthcare? Too expensive. Old age pensions? Are you crazy? Union rights and workplace safety laws? Those cost money you know. Infrastructure investments? The cupboard is bare.

How is it that we used to have all these things and now, when our economies are bigger and richer than they used to be, we can’t afford them anymore?

/I know why obviously, Thatcher and Reagan fucked the kids, but I wish someone in the media would point this out occasionally.

82

stevenjohnson 03.14.15 at 2:05 am

In 1971, faking ideals was useful for propagandizing against communism. The market’s collapsed now.

But the notion that academia isn’t building dream palaces any more doesn’t hold water I think. Libertarian and conservative ideal theory seems to be a thriving industry. The ideals of a permanent class society with endless US military domination of the planet may not be attractive to some of us, but they are ideals.

83

John Quiggin 03.15.15 at 3:35 am

One version of what I take to be Chris’ point

Rawls could (or thought he could) do ideal theory without talking about a political strategy – things were moving in the right direction, and the details could be left to those involved in the political process.

Today, ideal theory (at least of any version more attractive than those mentioned @82) has to be either

* combined with a political strategy involving (at a minimum), radical transformation or replacement of the existing centre-left/social-democratic parties
* consciously utopian, setting out an ideal which will hopefully inspire political action

84

david 03.15.15 at 1:11 pm

those criteria, stated alone, would include New Labour/DLC transformations of then-existing centre-left/social-democratic parties…!

85

ZM 03.16.15 at 12:09 pm

John Quiggin,

“Today, ideal theory (at least of any version more attractive than those mentioned @82) has to be either

* combined with a political strategy involving (at a minimum), radical transformation or replacement of the existing centre-left/social-democratic parties
* consciously utopian, setting out an ideal which will hopefully inspire political action”

2. It is quite hard to make up a utopia. We were set to make up utopias in a class once, and I’m not sure anyone really had their hearts in their final utopias to be honest — although this may have been because the class was called The Architecture of Wishful Thinking, and we started with More’s satire and then looked at all the subsequent great men’s failed utopias littering history.

1. Over Summer one of your colleagues on the Climate Council, Tim Flannery, recently wrote an article in The Monthly on making a new progressive political made up of internet commenter Cincinnati (the name was my favourite part — it is the plural of a Roman statesman which I guess is where the city got its name from).
His idea was that people would come to agree on policies by internet commenting — and these would become the Cincinnati Party’s policies. And if commenters were well enough trusted by the other Cincinnati commentariat then they could run for preselection and Parliament.
But it is quite hard to come to agreement on internet comment threads — so what would happen then? I do not think Tim Flannery is familiar with Brett Bellmore ;)

Comments on this entry are closed.