A question about referendums

by Harry on November 15, 2018

If you want to discuss Brexit, what’s going on, etc, please go to JQ’s thread. I have a question for those of you who know about referendums (referenda?) and/or surveys either through study or experience.

Several times recently, I’ve heard politicians say that it is obvious that a 3-option referendum is impossible. The obvious reason they say this is that they want to ensure that the (from their point of view) worst option is off the table: Brexiteers want “this deal or none” and Remainers want “This deal or stay”. Sensible enough. But, is there any other reason not to have a 3-option referendum, in which people rank their preferences, and if no option gets a majority, the second preference of those whose option comes third get redistributed?

Obviously its possible. I can think of actual reasons why it might be undesirable (eg, maybe people can’t cope with three options, or maybe there’s a reason to think that there’s something undemocratic about it, or that Current Deal would lose against either No Deal or Remain in 2-way votes, but would beat both of them in a 3-way vote even with 2nd-preferences redistributed), but have no idea whether these reasons have any basis in reality.

{ 48 comments }

1

Murali 11.15.18 at 6:15 pm

Isn’t there a worry that there might be Arrow-style cyclical preference rankings?

i.e. a majority would prefer A to B. A majority would prefer B to C and a majority would prefer C to A.

2

Oriol Mirosa 11.15.18 at 6:26 pm

On October 9th, 2016 (almost a year before the referendum that led to the current crisis in Catalonia, with politicians and civil society leaders jailed and the autonomy suspended by the Spanish government for a few months), the Catalan Government held a ‘consultation’ with a two-step question. First, people were asked: ‘Do you want Catalonia to be a state?’ If the answer was yes, then there was a second question: ‘Do you want this state to be independent?’

This clearly was a way to get federalist parties (such as the Catalan Socialist Party, which is federalist at least in principle) to support the consultation by giving them an option that they could agree with. People would then support one of three options: ‘Yes Yes’, ‘Yes No’, or ‘No’ in the consultation. Of course, this nuance disappeared from the October 1st, 2017 referendum, but that’s a whole other issue.

3

Marcus Pivato 11.15.18 at 7:06 pm

Hi Harry,

This is basically a question about social choice theory. Of course, a three-option (or four-option, or whatever) referendum is not “impossible”. The problem is that there are many different voting rules you could use for such a referendum, and there is no consensus which of these is the “best” or “correct” voting rule.

For a two-option referendum, one can make a fairly compelling argument for simple majority vote: under reasonable assumptions, and assuming there is no obvious asymmetry between the two options, simple majority vote is the unique best voting system. (There are theorems that state this formally.)

However, once you move to three or more options, there are an infinity of possible voting rules, each of which can claim to be “democratic” in some sense. All of these rules have good arguments in their favour, but all of them also have major weaknesses. For example, all of them can produce “perverse outcomes” (e.g. one option wins because the opposition was “split”; or a certain option that would have won becomes a loser after it gains more support; or some voters actually can get a better outcome for themselves by not voting, etc.). One major concern is that all of these rules are vulnerable to strategic voting.

What this means in practice is that there will always be some questions about the legitimacy of a three-outcome referendum. The losing side can always argue that the result is not legitimate —does not “really” reflect the Will of the People —because the wrong voting rule was used, some people voted strategically, etc.

You might think, “Why not just use Plurality Rule? It is simple, well-understood, widely used, and generally accepted.” But it turns out that, on closer inspection, Plurality Rule is actually one of the worst voting rules you could possibly use. (This, compounded with first-past-the-post regional representation, explains a lot of the problems with certain Western democracies, in my opinion.)

Social choice theorists have been studying this question for close to seventy years now (or seven hundred years, if you include the early work of Ramon Llull and Nicolaus Cusanus), and they still can’t come up with a really compelling argument that voting rule X is the best rule. (It’s like the old joke, “If you laid all the economists in the world end-to-end, they still wouldn’t reach a conclusion.”)

For Presidential elections in several countries (e.g. France), the voting rule is plurality rule with a run-off vote between the two front-runners. While this system has its problems, it also has much to recommend it: it is simple, well-understood, and guarantees that in the end, the winning option must be supported by a strict majority of the voters. If the UK was going to try for a three-outcome referendum, this might be the least-bad option.

4

Marcus Pivato 11.15.18 at 7:08 pm

Hi Harry,

This is basically a question about social choice theory. Of course, a three-option (or four-option, or whatever) referendum is not “impossible”. The problem is that there are many different voting rules you could use for such a referendum, and there is no consensus which of these is the “best” or “correct” voting rule.

For a two-option referendum, one can make a fairly compelling argument for simple majority vote: under reasonable assumptions, and assuming there is no obvious asymmetry between the two options, simple majority vote is the unique best voting system. (There are theorems that state this formally.)

However, once you move to three or more options, there are an infinity of possible voting rules, each of which can claim to be “democratic” in some sense. All of these rules have good arguments in their favour, but all of them also have major weaknesses. For example, all of them can produce “perverse outcomes” (e.g. one option wins because the opposition was “split”; or a certain option that would have won becomes a loser after it gains more support; or some voters actually can get a better outcome for themselves by not voting, etc.). One major concern is that all of these rules are vulnerable to strategic voting.

What this means in practice is that there will always be some questions about the legitimacy of a three-outcome referendum. The losing side can always argue that the result is not legitimate —does not “really” reflect the Will of the People —because the wrong voting rule was used, some people voted strategically, etc.

You might think, “Why not just use Plurality Rule? It is simple, well-understood, widely used, and generally accepted.” But it turns out that, on closer inspection, Plurality Rule is actually one of the worst voting rules you could possibly use. (This, compounded with first-past-the-post regional representation, explains a lot of the problems with certain Western democracies, in my opinion.)

Social choice theorists have been studying this question for close to seventy years now (or seven hundred years, if you include the early work of Ramon Llull and Nicolaus Cusanus), and they still can’t come up with a really compelling argument that voting rule X is the best rule. (It’s like the old joke, “If you laid all the economists in the world end-to-end, they still wouldn’t reach a conclusion.”)

For Presidential elections in several countries (e.g. France), the voting rule is plurality rule with a run-off vote between the two front-runners. While this system has its problems, it also has much to recommend it: it is simple, well-understood, and guarantees that in the end, the winning option must be supported by a strict majority of the voters. If the UK was going to try for a three-outcome referendum, this might be the least-bad option.

(apologies if this comment appears twice)

5

Howard Frant 11.15.18 at 7:31 pm

Not an expert, but didn’t you people just recently have a referendum on what you call the Alternative Vote? (Answer: Not unless you call 2011 recent.) I don’t see any reason why it should be different for issues than candidates. Of course, it failed, so maybe people just don’t like this, but maybe whatever the opposite is of “Familiarity breeds contempt.”

6

Tzimiskes 11.15.18 at 8:52 pm

God, I hope we live in a world where people can cope with three options.

7

Mat 11.15.18 at 8:52 pm

No personal expertise, but I read the article below on The Conversation recently. In a nutshell, it says that deciding on the winner of a three-way referendum is a hard problem in social choice theory
https://theconversation.com/want-a-brexit-deal-referendum-a-major-voting-problem-is-being-overlooked-102678

8

Craig 11.15.18 at 9:26 pm

Approval voting is another possibility: of the three options, pick the one or two that are acceptable. Either way to put three options on the ballot is more democratic than arbitrarily leaving one off. If bills must be passed before three options can be allowed on a referendum that could be a reason to say three options are impossible now. If voting machines are not set up for rank choice voting, then the argument may be the machines cannot be adapted in time for the vote. In that case approval voting may be easier to implement quickly.

9

Dragon-King Wangchuck 11.15.18 at 9:57 pm

Instant run-off referenda? That would be new to me. I think it wouldn’t be considered valid because referenda are already “complicated” enough. The idea of referenda is to get the will of the people on a question – it should be straightforward and simple.

In Canada we have the Quebec Reference Case and the Clarity Act to address our Referendum Issue. It mandates that referenda questions need to be clear.

That’s how it should go. If you are going to go full plebiscite, you need to be able to clearly state your question in a way that the least capable but still qualified voter can understand. I think that precludes having instant run-off or single transferable vote or any other second choice mechanism. And I don’t think a plurality among multiple options is compelling enough for referenda. So it has to be Yes or No.

10

Gareth Wilson 11.15.18 at 10:07 pm

The stakes were a lot lower, but the first New Zealand flag referendum had five choices for a new flag. It worked by the Australian system: rank the flags, but you don’t have to assign a rank to all of them. I’m not sure how many people realised that if there was a flag they especially hated, they should leave it unranked rather than ranking it 5.

11

Dipper 11.16.18 at 6:17 am

With regards to the UK having a 3-way referendum on Brexit, there are several issues with this.

1. The referendum is being proposed to avoid implementing the result of a previous referendum. This is a never-ending series.

2. The three-way choice is being touted to split the Leave vote and make it impossible for Leave to win. Leavers may see this coming, say this is a biased poll and not vote, resulting in grievance being built into the UK political system.

3. The EU is a constantly changing thing. Do we have a referendum for every change? If not then very soon you are in “we didn’t vote for this” territory.

My view is that unless referenda are an integral part of your constitution, you should avoid them if at all possible.

12

bad Jim 11.16.18 at 7:45 am

For what it’s worth, in the other thread it’s been asserted that given a choice between remain, the deal on offer, and no deal, remain would win a majority.

13

Dipper 11.16.18 at 7:45 am

… and the referendum we are being asked to consider now is one that requires us to approve a legal agreement that runs to over 500 pages. Seriously … that is why we elect people to represent us isn’t it?

14

PeteW 11.16.18 at 8:26 am

@Dipper

“1. The referendum is being proposed to avoid implementing the result of a previous referendum. This is a never-ending series.”

Experience suggests not. When referenda in Ireland (twice) and Denmark were essentially re-run, the second votes not only reversed the original decision and produced a greater majority on a higher turnout but sealed the matter – none has since been rerun a third time.

“2. The three-way choice is being touted to split the Leave vote and make it impossible for Leave to win. Leavers may see this coming, say this is a biased poll and not vote, resulting in grievance being built into the UK political system.”

Every single opinion poll in 2018, bar two nine months ago which were 50-50, suggests Remain has majority support in the country. The biggest, this month’s Survation poll of 20,000 people, gives Reman an 8-point lead. If you want to avoid ‘grievance’, I would suggest not following a course of major political change that the majority of the people oppose.

‘3. The EU is a constantly changing thing. Do we have a referendum for every change? If not then very soon you are in “we didn’t vote for this” territory.’

Then you can vote for an MEP who promises to oppose or reverse that thing you ‘didn’t vote for’ , and for a political party that will do does likewise in the Council of Ministers. That’s democracy.

15

TM 11.16.18 at 8:34 am

3-option referendums are nothing special. An example is the practice of putting a proposal and counter-proposal to referendum. For example a Popular Initiative in Switzerland, after gathering the required number of signatures, first is debated by the government and then by Parliament. Parliament can approve it, reject it, or offer a counter-proposal. In the latter case, the initiators may withdraw the initiative in favor of the counter-proposal or both proposals are put to referendum. Voters then have three votes: yes or no to proposal A, yes or no to proposal B, and they can state a preference in case both proposals reach a majority. So there are three clear options: Status quo, proposal A, proposal B. (https://de.wikipedia.org/wiki/Volksinitiative_(Schweiz))

Some other jurisdictions allow this practice. There is absolutely nothing problematic about it.

16

faustusnotes 11.16.18 at 9:04 am

I reckon on the back of Dipper’s logic that we should ban boxers from throwing in the towel. It’s just being proposed to avoid implementing the result of the boxer’s previous decision to get in the ring. What a never-ending series! No adult should ever be allowed to discover that their decision was the wrong one and back out of it. Whether it’s a boxer getting in the ring and finding out he’s being pummeled; a girl going back to a guy’s apartment and discovering he’s a serial killer; a nation voting for a leader and finding out they don’t like him after a year or three; or a nation voting to leave a trading bloc and discovering that the detail of the process is not in their best interests – adults should never, ever be allowed to go back on bad decisions.

17

TM 11.16.18 at 9:04 am

The above explained procedure in my view is way clearer and makes democratically more sense than a three way ranked alternative. The assumption is that the proposals go in the same direction but one is more radical while the other is more of a compromise so radical voters can support the radical proposal but also support the compromise in order to get at least moderate change. Normally the compromise is more likely to win. However if some radical voters really don’t like the compromise, they may split the “change” vote and thus help the status quo to win.

In the Brexit case, the status quo would be Remain and the proposals would be “Leave with Deal” or “Leave no deal”. Ardent Brexiteers would vote for both proposals and state a preference for either. Remainers would vote Remain and probably state a preference for Deal over No Deal. Suppose there still is a majority for Leave (probably not the case), almost all of them would have to be prepared to vote Yes twice in order to ensure that at least one (probably Deal) wins. But that seems unlikely since at least some Brexiteers would prefer the status quo over No Deal but some others passionately hate the Deal.

Generally I agree that it is problematic to use direct democratic instruments when they are not part of the constitutional tradition. Britain should either never have gone down that path, or should have adopted a constitutional framework that specifies when and how referenda are to be used. Switzerland has a long tradition in that respect but they too continue to learn. The procedure explained above was adopted (at the federal level) only 30 years ago, before that voters could only make one choice. This usually favored the status quo.

18

TM 11.16.18 at 9:07 am

Btw (last remark) it often strikes me here on CT how little Anglophones seem to know about the constitutional and political traditions of other countries. It really helps to be able look beyond one’s own nose, folks.

19

engels 11.16.18 at 10:05 am

My view is that unless referenda are an integral part of your constitution, you should avoid them if at all possible.

Thus spake Dipper

20

MisterMr 11.16.18 at 11:10 am

In Italy there are 2 types of referenda:

1) “consultivo” [advisory]: it’s basically a glorified opinion poll. It’s the kind of referendum like the brexit one.

2) “abrogativo” [abrogative]: this is actually binding for parliament and the government, however can only be used to cancel a law or part of a law.
This kind of referendum will have a question like this:

“would you like to abrogate act XX of 1975 access of the UK to the EU?”

or also like this:

“In the law XX of 1975, at the third paragraph that says everyone and his dog have to eat strawberry on sunday morning do you want to abrogate the words and his dog?”

I always wondered why only abrogative referenda are binding, but after looking at the brexit thing, I think that this is clear: the abrogative question is by its nature very specific, and it leads to no doubts to the legal implementation of the referendum results, whereas “propositive” referenda, like “should we join the EU?”, are more problematic because of the various possible implementations some will be seen as a betrayal of the original vote (eg., maybe I vote yes to the question “should we join the EU” but then when I realize the EU asks for the UK to send seven vigins as a sacrifice every seven years I see it as a betrayal).

This kind of abrogative referenda though have a problem, which is that generally the question is so specific, and relative to an article of a law that nobody knows, that usually voters have to choose based on the explanations given by politicians and journalists, that generally are biased or at the minimum reflect their own perspective.

Going back to the original question of the post, the problem is this:

A referendum can be binding only to the degree that the question on the ballot is really specific, so that there are no doubts about its implementation.
But a question that can have more than a yes/no answer will rarely be so clear cut that you can have a binding referendum; non-binding referenda are basically similar to an opinion poll exactly because in the end the implementation can vary a lot.

For example, suppose that you have a referendum that hase these 3 choiches:

1) Accept the deal
2) Revoke A50
3) Refuse the deal, but don’t revoke A50

What does choice (3) mean? Is this really no deal? What if the EU offers another deal, should we have a new referendum?
What does choice (2) mean? What if the EU says that the UK cannot revoke A50 unilaterally, and asks for the UK to drop the rebate?
Choice (1) is clear, but only works as long as the deal is unchanged (that we don’t know because EU states have not yet formally accepted it).

So the complexity of the situation, that make multiple choices possible, also make a clear cut referendum an impossibility, IMHO.

21

MisterMr 11.16.18 at 11:20 am

@TM 17

“In the Brexit case, the status quo would be Remain and the proposals would be “Leave with Deal” or “Leave no deal”.”

My understanding is that the status quo would be no deal, since A50 has already been triggered.
I say this because while this doesn’t change the logic of your argument, it shows that the situation is complex legally, in such a way that makes a referendum difficult.

This doesn’t mean that it is impossible, but it means that whomever wins the losers will never fully accept the result (as is already happening with the brexit referendum, anyway).

22

James Quan-Thomas 11.16.18 at 12:57 pm

Harry,

Thanks for posting this article. It was thinking about the problem you’ve raised that led me to discovering cardinal voting, of which I had never before heard and which now seems like an obvious ingredient in a democratic system aiming to adequately satisfy preferences! Obviously, this will seem like a rediscovery of the rudiments of counting to academics in the field, but it has excited me and so I’m hoping that someone will indulge me!

So! Say that we had a four-way referendum (let’s include EFTA/EEA) in which all participants could give every option a cardinal score between, say, ’10’ and ‘-5’. There is no ‘points limit’, they can, for instance, score three options ’10’ and one ‘-5’, if that best reflects their preferences. Highest number wins. All of this has the additional merit of appearing to me to be much more readily intelligible, than, say, STV.

Could anyone talk me through the specific pitfalls of that voting scheme, which seems to me so much better than either plurality or ranked majority voting?

23

Salem 11.16.18 at 2:04 pm

Why would you hold a referendum in the first place? Presumably it’s to legitimise a decision. There is no “will of the public” to be discovered, it’s just answers to poll questions. And the subtext here is finding a way to block Brexit – unlike Dipper I don’t find that illegitimate, but the Commons already has all the power it needs to do so. However, MPs sense – rightly! – that they’d be hammered at the polls for their betrayal. So any referendum that might undo Brexit would have to have at least as much political legitimacy as the original referendum, or it would fail to accomplish its task.

Suppose the voters were to break down as follows, which is pretty plausible:
45% No deal, second choice May’s deal.
15% May’s deal, second choice Remain.
40% Remain, second choice May’s deal.

No Deal is the plurality winner. Remain is the STV winner. May’s deal is the Condorcet winner – i.e. it beats every other option in a head-to-head. All have pretty good arguments. So who should win? Now, maybe this wouldn’t be so bad if we had a long history of such referenda, but we don’t. We would be making up the rules on the fly. Worse, we would have polling data, so the rules would be being made up on the fly not by disinterested parties based on abstract principles, but by partisans based on how much advantage said rules would give them. And even if we could somehow agree in such a partisan atmosphere (as I think we should) that Condorcet is the fairest and most legitimising procedure, we still have to ask why these are the options. Why isn’t “renegotiate the deal” an option, for instance? I strongly suspect that this would be more popular than any of your three options…

This will not achieve any popular legitimacy, unless somehow one option manages to win an absolute majority. And if one option could win an absolute majority, we don’t need 3 options to begin with.

Given the subtext, the referendum would presumably be set up with rules designed to favour the Remain outcome, so we would end up right where we are now – a House of Commons with a majority of members who would like to Remain, but who will lose their seats to justified popular anger if they vote that way. Why not just have a referendum between May’s deal and Remain and be done with it?

24

TM 11.16.18 at 2:15 pm

@21: You are correct that the situation is complicated. But to say that “Leave no deal” is the status quo can’t be right since currently, the UK still IS a member of the EU. And one could question whether the government declaration to trigger Art. 50 has the force of law since the courts have decided that any agreement with the EU needs parliamentary approval. The problem really is that the UK constitutional system is messed up. Can the government really cancel a decades-old treaty of vital importance for the nation with a simple letter sent by the Prime Minister, without even parliamentary consultation? Apparently it can but it shouldn’t be able to.

Anyway, for the purposes of holding a legitimate referendum, it is crucial that the options are clearly stated. As others have noted, that simply wasn’t the case in 2016. A referendum about May’s deal – whatever the procedural details – would at least have the virtue that voters would know approximately what they were voting for or against.

In any meaningful referendum, the status quo must be one option for the simple reason that the status quo is what people know and are able to evaluate. The status quo, as noted, still is EU membership. A referendum with only the choice between two different Leave options would be farcical and an abuse of the referendum process.

25

TM 11.16.18 at 2:21 pm

22: One can invent interesting voting procedures and have mathematical fun with them but I would really start with getting informed about those that have already been tried in the real world and have stood the test of time. Many political problems that Angloamericans are wrestling with have already been solved elsewhere.

Take this seriously, CT folks. Get to know the rest of the world at least a bit before daydreaming all those castles in the air.

26

Brett Dunbar 11.16.18 at 5:32 pm

@22

The big problem with cardinal voting systems such as Borda count and approval voting is that they allow lower preferences to count against higher preferences. If you use them in meaningful elections you get major tactical voting problems. With AV your lower preferences only come into play if your higher preferences have already been eliminated. Which avoids the paradoxical incentives of cardinal systems.

27

Marcus Pivato 11.16.18 at 5:36 pm

Hi James,

I’m a big fan of “Cardinal Voting” (also called “Range Voting”, “Evaluative Voting”, or “Score Voting”). There is a little bit of research on this voting rule in the social choice theory theory literature, but not very much. As you say, it seems to be “obviously” a good idea. But it runs into two serious problems.

First, it is not clear how to interpret the scores that the voters assign to alternatives. For example, suppose scores are on a scale from 0 to 10, and I assign alternative A a score of 2, alternative B a score of 3, and alternative C a score of 9. What exactly does this mean? Clearly, it means that I like C more than B, and B more than A. But does it mean that I like C “three times as much” as B? It’s not clear that this even makes any sense. Does it mean that my preference for C over B is “three times as strong” as my preference for B over A? Again, it’s not clear how to interpret such a statement.

Since the meaning of the scores is ambiguous, it is difficult to mathematically justify one particular way of aggregating them over another way. For example, the “obvious” thing to is to add the scores, as you propose. But why add them? Why not add the squares of the scores instead? Why not multiply them?

Furthermore, since the meaning of the scores is ambiguous, there is a concern that different voters will interpret them differently. For example, suppose that I vote as described above. Meanwhile, you assign alternative C a score of 2, alternative B a score of 5, and alternative A a score of 8. Clearly, I feel that C > B > A, whereas you think that C < B < A. But should we argue that your preference for B over C is “three times as strong” as my preference for B over A? Perhaps you just interpret the numbers in a different way than I do, and actually the intensity of your preferences for C > B > A is exactly the same as the intensity of my preferences for C < B < A.

The fact that there is no obvious way to answer these questions makes social choice theorists nervous, and has caused many of them to just avoid this voting rule altogether.

(One way to interpret these scores is as expressions of voters’ cardinal utility functions, so that Cardinal Voting is a sort of “utilitarianism”. But there is no guarantee that the voters themselves will interpret their scores in this way. And even if they did, this raises questions about the correct way to make “interpersonal comparisons” of cardinal utility. So it does not really solve the problem.)

A second problem is that if voters vote strategically, then they will not use the full expressive power of the scores anyways. Suppose there are six alternatives, A, B, C, D, E, and F, and suppose that my preferences are A< B< C< D< E< F . Suppose that I believe (based on public opinion polls, etc.) that the two alternatives most likely to win are B and D. Then it is not hard to see that my optimal “strategic” vote is as follows: assign A and B the minimum possible score (i.e. 0), and assign D, E and F the maximum possible score (i.e. 10). (Strategically speaking, I can assign C any score I want, since it is unlikely to win anyways. So I lose nothing by being honest in my assessment of C).

If everyone votes like this, then “Cardinal Voting” essentially devolves into the “Approval Voting” rule, where voters simply assign a score of either 1 or 0 (i.e. “yes” or “no”) independently to each alternative. There is nothing wrong with Approval Voting (indeed, it has lots of good features). But it seems a bit redundant to introduce a more complicated “Cardinal” rule if in practice it ends up being equivalent to Approval Voting.

28

James Quan-Thomas 11.16.18 at 9:36 pm

@ TM, 25

To be clear, I thought that your contribution, @15 and 17, was one of the most useful and pertinent in this discussion, and came closest to answering Harry’s question, alongside Marcus’ reference to the French run-off system.

I don’t know that exploring different models equates to not taking the issue seriously, though. There doesn’t actually seem to me to be much that is abstract or ivory-towered about what I proposed, and it strikes me that exploring different alternatives that satisfy our intuitive requirements of ‘fairness’ is a valuable activity in its own right because it allows us to clarify what we are looking for and what procedures can be used to attain it. I object a bit to the tone of dismissiveness towards theory, which I am sure you didn’t wholly intend. You’re certainly right that something that we know has functioned or is already functioning in the real world has an additional recommendation of validity, and that historical and contemporary voting models therefore deserve our special attention. And I am sure that the anglophone world does often appear (because it is!) frustratingly insulated, and I certainly value the contribution you have made, and my own digression doesn’t mean that I am not engaging with it and thinking about it. I certainly am.

@ Brett Dunbar, 26

I’m afraid you will have to lead me by the hand and show me what you mean with reference to the example I gave. I’m sure that you’re right, but I can’t think of what you could mean by ‘tactical voting’ in the system as I envisage it that wouldn’t actually amount to an anticipated and desirable feature. But that doesn’t mean that I’m not just being extremely dense!

@ Marcus, 27

Hi Marcus,

Thank you, I appreciate your taking the time to write a long and thoughtful reply!

I feel and fully appreciate the critique that aggregating individual scores into a total score assumes, or seems to assume, that the intervals between the scores are commensurate between individuals. (I took a psychology degree once upon a time, and at every turn reading about social choice theory I hear echoes of half-forgotten statistics lectures; in this case the discussion on likert scales, ordinal and interval data). I think, though, that provided that the case can be made that a scoring method does provide more precise expression of the relative intensity of preferences than ranking alone, one doesn’t necessarily have to go on to prove that it does so to the same degree with different people, or does so equally well with different people, desirable though those things would be. It might suffice that, where a person wants to express more precision than a ranked system, it affords that greater precision, information that in other voting systems would be anyway lost. Probably? I’m open to rejoinder, because I’m sure that there’s perverse outcomes hidden in here that I am happily avoiding looking square in the face.

You can aggregate the scores however you like, I should think, so long as you preserve all of the relative ratios between them, because that is the basic unit of data that the voters are communicating, right? Of course, any manipulation of the figures you’re going to do to interpret them should be transparent before voting begins, just as should apply with any voting system!

You’re also right that the very first thing that voter should do would be to assign their preferred outcome a 10 and their least preferred outcome a -5. If their main ambition was to avoid a particular outcome, then there would be a logic to then giving all other possibilities a 10 too, or, to win a particular outcome, all of the other possibilities a -5. In which case, as you point out, the ‘middle space’ is redundant.

But I think that it’s precisely this available redundancy that appeals to me in part. There’s bandwidth available in the vote to make more subtle gradations if and only if they are meaningful and necessary in the context of the particular vote. There could be a critique that this available redundant space could encourage some voters to use it when doing so isn’t in their interests. As with any voting method, it depends on literacy.

Maybe I haven’t grasped the extent of the objections you’ve very cogently raised, though as you say, you’re a fan yourself. But I have to admit to being quite pleased and surprised with the relative tameness of the objections you cite! It seems like a pretty good voting system, then? A surprisingly underadvocated one!

29

John Quiggin 11.17.18 at 5:35 am

“how little Anglophones seem to know about the constitutional and political traditions of other countries”

Australia is Anglophone, and we have tried just about every voting system under the sun: single and multi-member plurality, instant runoff (with or without full ranking), Hare-Clark (with and without Robson rotation), list systems and many more.

My favorite was the modified D’Hondt system – it came with a 15-page explanatory booklet which neither a PhD in economic theory, nor an Honours degree in pure maths enabled me to understand. It produced some bizarre results the only time it was tried (admittedly a bizarre election anyway) and was never used again.

It always amuses me to see fellow-Anglophones (some of whom aren’t too kind about Aussie intellectual ability) explain that instant-runoff is too hard for ordinary voters to understand.

30

Hidari 11.17.18 at 7:33 am

My question is much simpler: since when did referendumS become the acceptable plural?
When I was growing up, it was referendA.

Considering how many of these we are likely to have over the coming years and decades this does not seem to be to be quite as trivial a point as it might seem.

31

Brett Dunbar 11.17.18 at 8:23 am

The tactical voting problem in all cardinal voting systems comes from the lower preferences counting against higher preferences. This creates a perverse incentive to vote dishonestly.

An example using the modified borda count used in Eurovision. Say your national jury vote is honest and puts Serbia first (twelve points) and Sweden second (ten points). Add all the other jury and popular votes and Sweden wins by two points, the jury’s second-best outcome. If they had voted tactically given Sweden no points and still given Serbia twelve then Serbia wins by eight points. Which gives the jury’s preferred outcome.

While the exact details vary depending on which of the many cardinal voting systems you use they all have this problem.

32

Mike-SMO 11.17.18 at 8:33 am

The prior referendum voted “UK out of EU”. If the government “don’t wanna”, the government should resign allowing new elections. THAT referendum would be the only one that matters. Candidates can run on their belief on Brexit or some alternative plan.

The “government” asked the country what it wanted. The people answered that question. The government must comply or resign. The referendum was not some BS poll by a “bought and paid for media conglomerate”. The “government” arrogantly called for a “safe” referendum. They lost. Tough. Follow through on the vote or get out. No “do overs”.

Calling another referdum, of whatever form, is just deceit. It sounds like time for the “back benchers” to gin up their courage and serve the people of the UK.

33

eg 11.17.18 at 9:32 am

@Tzimiskes 6

You don’t live in America, I suppose, where it appears to be Team Pepsi vs Team Coke all the time everywhere?

34

ccc 11.17.18 at 9:46 am

Timely Larry Lessig piece on ranked-choice voting
https://eu.usatoday.com/story/opinion/2018/11/16/ranked-choice-voting-maine-protest-candidates-election-2018-column/2023574002/

Seems applicable also for referendums.

As a side note Lessig also makes what could be taken as a very interesting strategical point in favor of the US democratic party unilaterally adopting ranked-choice voting in its internal presidential candidate elections:
“And candidates would be disciplined not to denigrate at least the candidates whose votes they aspire ultimately to win. The party would leave the primary not bruised but emboldened. And the ultimate nominee would not have a year of vicious attacks gifted to her or his opponent.”

35

James Quan-Thomas 11.17.18 at 9:56 am

Okay, it’s taken me overnight, but I understand the force of one of the objections now!

Because it’s one-round and winner-takes-all, as Marcus says there is an incentive for people to not only express their preferences but to bake their predictions of other people’s votes into their own, by systematically overstating their preference for options that they believe are likely to be widely popular. This doesn’t necessarily come at any direct cost to their ‘real’ favourite, which they can also rate ’10’ (the equivalent of a ‘hopeless cause’ STV first preference). But it does distort the information they provide, which the French run off model, and the Swiss model both are at pains to account for. The French run-off model with its famous “first round to say what you want, second round to do what you must”, the Swiss by establishing completely independent votes for each discrete outcome. I think that this is a very serious weakness of the system I proposed as I proposed it.

36

James Quan-Thomas 11.17.18 at 10:49 am

@Brett

Yes, right, thank you for explaining, I see what you’re saying! Of course, Eurovision is presumably especially bad because the voting is stepwise — people have perfect knowledge of their vote’s effects on running totals at the time of casting. But this is only an extreme manifestation of a problem that is intrinsic. The more knowledge people have, the less they candidly say what they want and the more they treat their vote as an instrument for moving the totals in the direction they need them to go. That’s a problem, definitely.

37

TM 11.17.18 at 11:19 am

29: “Australia is Anglophone, and we have tried just about every voting system under the sun” Point taken.

“My favorite was the modified D’Hondt system – it came with a 15-page explanatory booklet which neither a PhD in economic theory, nor an Honours degree in pure maths enabled me to understand.”

Interesting, the original D’Hondt system was used (? at least it was named after) Jefferson more than 200 years ago. It was used in Germany up to 1985 and replaced by Hare-Niemayer (for Anglos: Hamilton), which is more complicated but fairer to small parties. I have heard people (well, Americans) complain about the complexity of these algorithms but they really don’t matter to the voter (at least as long as there is a reasonable number of seats to assign). What voters need to know is that seats are assigned approximately proportionally (and in the German case that small parties under 5% vote share get nothing).

32: Two problems:
– The constitutional status of the 2016 referendum is entirely undefined
– The question put to the voters in 2016 doesn’t meet the requirement of clarity. They voted (by a tiny margin) against the status quo but not for any specified alternative.

38

Marcus Pivato 11.17.18 at 11:36 am

Hi Brett (@26 and @31) and James (@35)

It is important to note that, once you have more than two alternatives, all voting rules are susceptible to strategic voting, in one way or another. (There are theorems that state this precisely.) This includes Alternative Vote (also known as Ranked-choice Vote, Single-Transferable Vote, Instant-Runoff Vote, etc.). Thus, the question is not whether such-and-such voting rule is susceptible to strategic voting, but how much of a problem this is likely to be in reality. How easy is it for voters to vote strategically? In what fraction of (plausible) scenarios will this occur? How big is the gap between their strategic vote and their honest vote? How much of a difference is it likely to make to the outcome?

For example, in rules which require voters to express a strict preference order over the alternatives (e.g. Alternative Vote, Borda rule, Condorcet methods, etc.) voters will often have a strategic incentive to actually reverse their preferences (e.g. I actually prefer A over B, but I strategically claim to prefer B over A). In the case of a rule like Borda, it is quite easy to construct scenarios where this will happen; it is likely to be a significant problem. (When Condorcet raised this objection, Borda responded weakly, “My scheme is intended only for honest men.”) In contrast, in cardinal voting rules, there is never a good strategic reason to “reverse” preferences in this way; at most, you might want to “exaggerate” your preferences by assigning dishonestly high or low values to some alternatives (as explained in my previous post).

In Approval Voting, the scope for strategic voting is extremely limited; I can strategically claim to “approve” of some alternatives that I actually disapprove of, and vice-versa. There are actually relatively few scenarios where this seems to be advantageous, so people generally regard Approval Voting as not very susceptible to strategic voting.

In Alternative Vote, strategic voting is quite difficult in practice, because the complicated multi-round elimination procedure makes it a hard problem (in fact, an NP-complete problem) for a voter to figure out her optimal strategy. So in this sense, Alternative Vote is “resistant” to strategic voting. On the other hand, it is precisely this complexity which makes Alternative Vote unattractive in other ways, since the rule often responds in surprising (and even “perverse”) ways to changes in voters’ preferences, and it is difficult to explain ex post facto why candidate A won the election instead of B.

39

James Quan-Thomas 11.17.18 at 3:11 pm

I’d just like to thank Marcus again for taking the time to patiently share his expertise. I certainly feel that he’s clarified a lot for me.

To return to Harry’s opening question, then, it seems to me that if you have an uncontroversial ‘status quo’, the Swiss system is the gold standard. All options are discrete votes requiring their own majorities (no tactical voting), with a preference mechanism built in to adjudicate if multiple proposals get over the line. (The detail on the preference mechanism would be interesting – again, simple plurality?)

Unfortunately, the first referendum probably scuppered the ‘uncontroversial status quo’ criterion – we already voted to leave, so in the absence of a majority, would we stay in, or crash out? Making either a default would now seem like gerrymandering to a substantial part of the electorate.

The next alternative, then, would be a run-off system. Any one-round system would be susceptible to the following: a single poll, perhaps due to mere noise, shows one of the ‘remain-flavoured’ options and one of the ‘leave-flavoured’ options ahead of the others. Having only one shot at getting the most popular option, the two camps then begin to cluster around these positions, in an endless feedback loop, like a run on the banks in reverse. Run-off elections take the pressure off this. One of each kind of flavour will certainly make it through, so there’s space in the first round to be candid about what specifically you prefer.

All this having been said, if you’re considering a one-round, multiple choice election, consider cardinal systems! Provided that you’re willing to make the assumption that the intervals individuals leave between options reflect something, and that this is true between as within individual voters, cardinal systems are probably superior to ranked systems if we’re aiming to adequately reflect preferences, though they suffer some of the same weaknesses to tactical voting as the rest of their family.

Yeah?

40

TM 11.17.18 at 4:43 pm

“since when did referendumS become the acceptable plural”

What is the plural of “album”?

41

Brett Dunbar 11.17.18 at 5:26 pm

Ordinal voting state seem to have fewer perverse incentives than other systems. The biggest in practice in STV is placing a weak candidate you like first so if your real first preference are above quota before eliminations begin then your vote comes into play at a later stage at full value rather than as a fractional vote. Or you help get the weak candidate elected unexpectedly (this applies mostly if there are a relatively large number of available seats). Mostly however it is optimal to vote your real preferences as you would need a detailed knowledge of how other people are likely to vote.

Borda is a cardinal voting system, which means it has several perverse incentives that ordinal systems lack. The lower preferences counting against higher preferences is why they are rarely used for anything important.

Approval voting has the problem that it doesn’t account for relative preferences at all. It might benefit a disliked party to have a credible extremist party as no reasonable person would want the extremist elected they might approve all the moderate parties. Even ones they strongly dislike.

42

Scott P. 11.17.18 at 6:00 pm

The “government” asked the country what it wanted. The people answered that question.

Was it a well-formed question, though? If I run a referendum asking ‘should blue be abolished’, and the result is YES, what action(s) do you believe are incumbent upon the legislature?

43

Tom Hurka 11.17.18 at 6:08 pm

Re ccc and the Lessig piece:

Isn’t one of the reasons Trump won the Republican presidential nomination from a large field of candidates that the others expected him to fade and behaved nicely to him because they hoped to pick up his supporters afterward? In this case some more nastiness in the process would have been preferable.

44

ccc 11.17.18 at 10:55 pm

@43 Tom Hurka:

Possible, but I really have no clue in the extraordinary case of Trump. It sometimes feels like he wasn’t far from the truth when he said “I could stand in the middle of 5th Avenue and shoot somebody and I wouldn’t lose voters”.

But more generally I take your reply as a useful counterweight to Lessig’s argument in that negative campaigning in primaries could in some cases help detect and weed out truly nasty candidates.

Related on Trump and RCV: https://www.fairvote.org/simulating_instant_runoff_flips_most_donald_trump_primary_victories

45

Mike-SMO 11.17.18 at 11:05 pm

A/K/A #32
——————-
I have no idea of the “constitutional” status of a particular referendum or of any of the weird-&-wonderful voting/lottery systems under consideration here. The question was asked in the first referendum by the government, using governmentcreated text, using a polling system run by the government. The answer was “Brexit!”.

The governmentcould have delt with that issue in Parliament but took the time and expense to ask the populace directly. The government didn’t get the answer that it wished. Any “Brexit” was going to have costs to the economy and to the nation. The duty of the government in this, and most other issues, was to get as good of a solution as possible. All choices have “costs”.

It is fraudulent to now claim that the populace didn’t understand the issue, when you mean that they didn’t appreciate your preference. Actually, you don’t seem to understand the issue(s) that are important to the populace.

I have no idea about the details of “constitutionality”. I am reluctant to use the term such as “honor” in a political discussion. The government asked a question directly to the populace, presumably to get past party and donor issues. The government seems bound to go for the best Brexit deal that it can get in light of the answer that it receivedor to get out of the way and let someone else take care of the problem(s). It is clear that the government has refused to do anything, so far, to reduce the expected adverse impacts of a Brexit.

I suspect that the original referendum was a ploy to relieve pressure on the government that didn’t go as planned. Too bad! Since the government made an “unusual” move to get feedback directly from the populace, it would seem that the government is obliged to follow through with the response that they received. Otherwise, the question becomes, “Who is the supposedly representative government actually representing?”

Most of the conversation here seems to be about the lottery system most likely to get the result that the pro-EU faction wants. In my untutored opinion, that train has already left the station. A significant portion of the UK populace doesn’t want what you are selling.

46

engels 11.18.18 at 12:01 am

when did referendumS become the acceptable plural? When I was growing up, it was referendA.

When the proportion of British people who give a shit about Latin grammar dropped below some threshold.

47

John Quiggin 11.18.18 at 3:16 am

Most of the discussion has been in the abstract, so let’s look at the practicalities.

Assuming that the system is alternative vote/IRV, and that the alternatives are those set out by May: Her deal, No deal, No Brexit (ie revoke Article 50 declaration)*, it seems clear that No Brexit will get at least the 34 per cent needed to avoid elimination. If No Brexit gets a first round majority, there are no problems, so let’s assume that doesn’t happen.

Suppose everyone agrees on a left-right ranking from No Deal to No Brexit, with May’s deal in the centre. That is, any No Deal voter would prefer May to No Brexit and vice versa. That implies that, if No Brexit doesn’t win a majority in the first round, it will lose to May’s deal in the second, but might beat No Deal. I’ll assume that, since No Deal is, I think, too scary for most.

In this case, it makes sense for No Dealers to vote tactically for May’s deal in the first round, ensuring that May’s deal wins in the second round.

I don’t think this is the case, however. I think a lot of No Dealers would prefer staying in the EU to the “vassal state” offered by May. In that case, No Brexit beats either of the alternatives – it is what is called the Condorcet winner.

* How any of these choices actually play out depends, of course, on the response of the EU

48

craig 11.19.18 at 3:28 am

@43 @44
Trump won the primaries because of vote splitting and because we in US have the worst possible voting system.

Comments on this entry are closed.