G.A. Cohen on the output bias

by Chris Bertram on August 28, 2024

(Originally drafted for a conference at Frankfurt in 2018 to mark the 40th anniversary of Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence. I’ve done a bit of editing of my conference script and added a few footnotes etc, but it isn’t necessarily produced to the scholarly standards one might require of a journal article.)

In Karl Marx’s Theory of History, G.A. Cohen attributed many of the ills of capitalism to the market mechanism. Later in his career he came to see the market as practically ineliminable. Insofar as he was right about the market in his earlier work, it may turn out that the alternatives to capitalism he championed at the end of his life will also generate the pathology he deplored: the systematic bias in favour of output over leisure and free time. The following explores some of these tensions.

Introduction

In the second half of his career, G.A. Cohen concentrated his discussion of capitalism on its wrongs and injustices. According to his diagnosis, the primary injustice in capitalism arose from the combination of private property and self-ownership, which enables capitalists – who own the means of production – to contract with workers – who own only themselves and their labour power, on terms massively to the capitalists’ advantage. The workers, who produce nearly all of the commodities that possess value in a capitalist society, see the things that they have produced appropriated and turned against them as tools of exploitation and domination by the capitalists. But the wrongness and injustice of capitalism, the theft of what rightfully belongs to workers, is only one part of what is to be deplored about capitalism. In chapter 11 of Karl Marx’s Theory of History, a chapter where he went beyond the expository and reconstructive work he undertook earlier in the book, Cohen articulated a different critique, this time focused not on injustice but on the ills to which capitalism gives rise. In that chapter he attacks capitalism for stunting human potential through a bias towards the maximization of output, a bias which condemns human beings to lives dominated by drudgery and toil. Relatedly, he attacks capitalism both for stimulating demand for consumption that adds little of real value to people’s lives and because for damaging of the natural environment through pollution. In developing this critique, Cohen also notes that the bias towards output he identifies is celebrated by Max Weber as exemplifying rationality itself, a celebration which Cohen thought ideological and mistaken.1

Though both the wrongness and the badness of capitalism arise from the conjunction of private property and the market, it seems natural to emphasize the role of private property more in the production of injustice and to stress market relations more in the genesis of its badness. It is the fact of what the capitalists own that gives them decisive leverage over workers in the labour market, making exploitation within the workplace consequently possible; it is the market that compels everyone, capitalists and workers both on pain of extinction, to act in ways that end up being so destructive for human and planetary well-being.

This difference in effect between private property in the means of production on the one hand and the market on the other is potentially consequential in the following way: the elimination of private property in the means of production, as envisaged by market socialism, or its wide dispersal among individuals (as envisaged by some versions of a Rawlsian property-owning democracy) could put an end to capitalist injustice and exploitation. But insofar as market relations cannot be eliminated, the ills that arise purely or largely from those relations may also be ineliminable.

In chapter 11, Cohen attributes the output bias to market relations. Because at that stage of his career he had thought less about the arguments around planning and markets than he did later – as reflected, for example in his final work Why Not Socialism? – the chapter is far too sanguine about the prospects for escaping drudgery and excessive production. This optimism seems even more marked when we notice that Cohen is tacitly and unjustifiably presupposing in this chapter a framework for understanding social relations and political action that has as its principal players capitalists and workers on the territory of a single state and therefore neglects the contribution of interstate rivalry and other dimensions of the international order to the output bias.

Cohen’s argument comes in two parts. First, he diagnoses the bias towards greater output and consumption over leisure as having its roots in market competition. Second, he asks why this bias, which is a mere systemic tendency for certain effects to be realized, is in fact realized rather than counteracted by other pressures such as political and trade union action.

The output bias as a systemic tendency

In chapter 11, Cohen writes that he presents “contemporary ‘affluent’ capitalism as the climax of the history of use-value and exchange-value, and as the prelude to the suppression of exchange-value as regulator of the social organism.” (297). After an opening section in which he gives an idealized account of a sequence that leads from the very first human production (which aims at use-value) to modern capitalism that aims at the “appropriation of value, of money, of abstract wealth.” (302, citing Theories of Surplus Value ii, 503). In such a system, he argues,

Whatever goals a corporation has, it must, on pain of bankruptcy, obey the imperative: seek to expand the exchange value at your disposal. This holds whether firms aim at profit or at growth, for they are different modes of increasing exchange-value, and no firm can aim at neither. It also holds whether or not managerialist theses are true: whoever wields ultimate corporate power is constrained to favour decisions which enlarge the difference between M and M1. (302)

Capitalism, Cohen argues (following Marx), develops technological power “on an unprecedented scale, progressing at an unprecedented rate” “because the competitive position of its industrial decision-makers compels them to increase the productivity of the production processes” (303). He notes that such increases in productivity could in principle be directed in two ways. On the one hand, they could be used to reduce toil and to give people more leisure for the same level of output. On the other, those gains in productivity could be used to generate more output, with workers labouring just as much as they did before. (And, of course, some combination of the two is possible, with workers working a bit less than they had previously to produce more than they did before, though not as much as they could if their hours had remained undiminished.)

Cohen then makes the following claim, which he italicizes throughout to emphasize its importance to his argument:
Now capitalism inherently tends to promote just one of the options, output expansion, since the other, toil reduction, threatens a sacrifice of the profit associated with increased output and sales, and hence a loss of competitive strength. (304)

Supposing this claim to be true so that capitalism does indeed generate the output bias with its attendant pathologies, this does not establish that the abolition or supercession of capitalism would eliminate it. As Cohen puts it (313) capitalism might be a sufficient condition for the bias, but it might not be a necessary one. He observes that

Capitalism is a society whose production is governed by a capitalist principle and which exhibits a division between a capitalist and a labouring class. But capitalism’s preference for output depends largely on the first feature. We may envisage class undivided societies whose production follows the capitalist principle. (314)

He invites us to consider three such societies: first, “a market economy of self-employed producers who hire no labour”; second, “a set of firms each of which is wholly owned by its employees, who share fairly equally the firm’s income”; and a third, which Cohen calls “people’s capitalism” and which to my mind resembles Rawls’s “property-owning democracy”.2 This is a society which “differs from the second in that share ownership is not restricted to the employee’s firm. In addition, in this “Rawlsian” society, in order to keep things egalitarian, there is a duty of all to work and an income ceiling aimed at preventing the formation of distinct classes.” (314–5)

Cohen dismisses the first form of society as “incompatible with really advanced technology” and focuses his attention on forms two and three which he considers together.

In KMTH he argues both that there are no historical examples of such societies and also asserts that they are “not reasonable options now” (315). The argument to this effect is brief, but it is essentially that some firms would be more successful than others and that the unsuccessful ones would either be driven out of business or would end up as subordinated subcontractors of the successful ones. Although there could be institutional mechanisms, such as insurance schemes, that might mitigate these effects, they would either be unsuccessful in doing so or they would have the effect of undermining the fundamentally market character of the society.3

Contrasted with both capitalism and these hypothetical non-capitalist market societies is a non-market society with comprehensive economic planning in which “decision-makers are free, as far as systematic economic constraints are concerned, to choose between expanding output and reducing labour, when there is progress in productivity.” (315) Cohen concedes, in passing that actual planned economies have been rather disappointing in their preference for output over leisure. (And in fact we now know, perhaps better than we appreciated in 1978, that in their attempts to compete with the West, Soviet planners both increased burdensome toil and artificially restricted consumption whilst generating enormous environmental problems.) But he claims that “Political change in the Soviet Union could lead to altered priorities with no dramatic reshaping of its economic system.” (316)

Could social democracy mitigate the output bias?

I shall assume that Cohen is right about the tendency of market societies, including, and especially, capitalist societies to promote output over leisure and hence to produce longer working hours than would obtain if productivity gains were channeled into freeing people from burdensome toil rather than maintaining the toil and producing more stuff. Still, as mentioned earlier, this is a mere tendency which might not be realized in practice if countervailing forces were to prevent this from happening. Such countervailing forces might have their origins in the desire of workers to have more leisure and forego consumption to get it, and such desires might become effective through social-democratic legislation, through trade union action or even through the market power of some, probably skilled, workers who could insist on a shorter working week as one of their contractual terms. Cohen suggests that if such restrictions on working time could be generally enforced, then they might take place with little or no detriment to capitalist firms because the restrictions would apply to all such firms and no firm would be put at a competitive disadvantage by them. 4
That capitalism has the bias that Cohen attributes to it in actuality and not just in theory seemed evident to him from an examination of recent history. Though workers were not working such long hours in 1978 as they did in 19th century factories, working hours had not fallen all that much since the 1920s and these are reductions from an extreme lengthening of the working day that capitalism itself had caused. Allowing for things like religious festivals in the Middle Ages, Cohen claims that modern workers now (that is, in 1978) work as long as medieval peasants did.

Nor have things let up much since the publication of Karl Marx’s Theory of History.5 Enormous gains in productivity consequent on revolutions in computing and information technology have typically been directed not at the relief of burdensome toil, but, among other things at increasing the intensity and sometimes duration of labour through greater control and surveillance of the workforce, as with pickers in Amazon warehouses. Sarah O’Connor reports in the Financial Times :

In the UK, the government funds a vast survey of UK workers every five years to keep track of how the quality of work is changing. The latest results show Britons are working harder than at any time in the past 25 years, to tighter deadlines and with less autonomy.6

Even as the nature of the workforce has changed, with fewer people in advanced capitalist economies engaged in industrial production than before and more in “white-collar” jobs, the character of jobs in the expanded sectors has become more routinized and proletarianized in character and experience. There were far fewer university professors, for example, in 1950 than there are today, but those that there were worked shorter hours and were subject to less controlling management than the expanded army of university teachers are today (and we are, of course, a relatively privileged sector).

Capitalism, Cohen argues, once had a progressive role. It was an “indispensable engine for producing material wealth from a position of scarcity.” But because of the output bias, capitalism cannot “realize the possibilities of liberation it creates”. “It brings society to the threshold of abundance and locks the door.” (306-7).

One way of explaining the failure of workers to push back on working time and to favour leisure over consumption is that they are merely duped by ideology to want more and more things rather than increased free time, even though more free time would be better for them than more things. Sensibly, Cohen doesn’t rely on such a claim though he thinks it has more going for it than people generally suppose.

What then is the explanation? Why do workers typically push for more consumption rather than for shorter hours? Here I think Cohen’s argument is untypically unclear. He tells us that workers do indeed want more goods (other things being equal) but it is also plain that they dislike the toil then need to engage in to get those goods and evidences that claim by making the point that if workers were granted money such that they didn’t need to work at their jobs, very few of them would choose to do so gratis, and there would be a dramatic decline in the amount of work done. His suggestion seems to be that since there is a permanent propaganda campaign in support of people getting more stuff and no corresponding campaign in favour of free time of the kind one can enjoy without extra spending, extra consumption always has a salience for people that additional leisure lacks.

I think Cohen’s uncharacteristically feeble discussion of this point can be explained in part by a blindspot in his thinking. First of all, he neglects the way in which states support and encourage consumer spending and simultaneously encourage a culture of work and effort through moralizing campaigns, stigmatization of “shirkers” and the like. Take the first of these elements: states help establish and support structures of lending to help people to do things like buy their own homes and then furnish their homes. They do this in a variety of ways, by providing support to banks and other financial institutions but also by giving borrowers all kinds of tax breaks. In order to buy the things they want, consumers have little choice but to borrow, but once they have borrowed they have to repay and repaying requires income, which requires work. Now perhaps workers could simply refuse the blandishments of capital and refuse to borrow in order to consume and then the option to work less would be more available to them. But I think this neglects the competitive and social aspects of consumption that Cohen rather dismissively refers to as “keeping up with the Joneses”. One need not be of a particularly competitive or comparative disposition to be caught up in social standards of self-presentation that are inherently comparative in nature, as Adam Smith knew in that famous passage about labourers being ashamed to appear in public without a linen shirt or, in some countries, leather shoes.7

Second, there is the question of why states support the bias towards output over leisure in the way that they do. Cohen would certainly have one part of the answer readily to hand given that the states with which he is concerned are capitalist states and capitalist states have as their primary function, in the historical materialist story he tells in KMTH, the defence and promotion of the interests of capital. Since capitalist firms prefer greater output to less, want their workers to put in more time and effort, to be “committed” and have the right attitudes, it is unsurprising that capitalist states echo and reinforce this preference. But were capitalist states isolated from one another, we could expect this tendency to be moderated. After all, the capitalist state also has the function of saving capitalists from large-scale collective action problems in which the pursuit of profit by each leaves them all worse off than they otherwise might be, and to this end states impose common standards and regulations on capitalists. Given that the output bias is systemically driven by competition among capitalist firms, it might be moderated by state-imposed restrictions on working hours that hold for all capitalists. (And indeed, historically, the state has imposed such limits on the employment of labour in order to prevent inter-capitalist competition from degrading, through overwork, the human capital on which capitalism depends.)

Unfortunately, Cohen writes, in this chapter at least, as if capitalist states and societies were isolated entities. The dramatis personae in his story are capitalist firms and workers co-existing within a single society. But societies are not isolated from one another and this matters in various different ways. First, inter-capitalist competition takes place across national boundaries, so the ability of states to mitigate that by enforcing common standards is limited. Second, the fact that capital is mobile across international boundaries strengthens the bargaining position of capitalists against workers, such that demand by workers to earn more or work less can often be credibly countered by a threat to move production to a different jurisdiction. Third, and I think this is of the greatest importance, states are and conceive themselves to be, in competition with one another. This means they care about their relative economic strength and wealth because this tends to translate to relative power in the international arena. This will lead them to favour increased output over increased leisure for their populations, at least up to the point where the physical capacities of potential soldiers are not too badly damaged. Insofar as increased consumption fosters economic development more generally, it will also lead them to favour consumption over leisure. But if it is necessary to suppress consumption also, perhaps to divert effort into infrastructure development or defence spending, states will do that too. Though Cohen’s attention was focused on pressures arising from competition among capitalist firms, it is plain that these competitive pressures among states also apply to non-market societies, hence the choice of the Soviet Union (as mentioned above) to promote hard work and labour discipline.

In the final substantive section of the chapter, Cohen takes issue with Max Weber for some remarks Weber makes which appear to identify the bias in favour of output over leisure with rationality as such. Weber comments on how, only a generation previously it was

futile to double the wages of an agricultural labourer in Silesia … in the hope of inducing him to increase his exertions. He would simply have reduced by half the work expended because with this half he would have been able [to earn as much as before]. (321)

Cohen was surely right about this, and indeed we see this Silesian behavior reproduced in more recent periods of capitalist society by individuals such as doctors in general practice in the UK’s National Health Service who, after securing a large increase paid for their services, were able to hire locums to do much of their work and to use the time saved to play some extra rounds on the golf course.

Cohen embraces the market
Central to Cohen’s case that capitalism exhibits a bias towards output and against leisure was the market mechanism. And we have seen that in Karl Marx’s Theory of History he dismisses as infeasible market-based alternatives to capitalism whilst suggesting that they too would exhibit the same bias as productive units were disciplined by market forces. There, it is a system of comprehensive planning that stands as feasible alternative to capitalism and as a society in which the choice to favour leisure over output is genuinely socially available. But at the end of his life Cohen had basically conceded that market mechanisms are indispensable in a complex society. In Why not Socialism? he writes:

… once we pass out of the sphere of need, or, more generally, of goods that everyone can be expected to want, to the wide sphere of optional commodities, and we pass increasingly to that as economies progress and as life therefore becomes easier and more elegant, it also becomes difficult to know what to produce, and how to produce it, without the device of market signals: very few socialist economists would now dissent from that proposition. (WnS, 60).

He had also cooled on central planning, writing:

Central planning, at least as practiced in the past, is, we now know, a poor recipe for economic success, at any rate once a society has provided itself with the essentials of a modern productive system. (WnS, 67).

In the light of the failures of central planning, Cohen’s revision of his opposition to the market is understandable. But as far as I know, he never revisited his claims about the output bias in the light of his subsequent embrace of the market, and that is a silence that his admirers have reason to be disappointed by.

Two conclusions

There seem to be two conclusions open to us on the basis of this discussion: call these the optimistic conclusion and the pessimistic conclusion. According to the optimistic conclusion, the variation in labour-time reduction in some countries and the remarkable gains made in some of those countries during the twentieth century, often at the behest of social-democratic governments and trade unions and made in the context of what have been essentially market-based economies, tells us that Cohen was wrong in some of his exposition. Even if market economies do have a bias towards output and consumption over leisure, there is more that we can do to tame them than Cohen thought and workers can and will use political action and trade union bargaining to reduce hours and to improve working conditions so that work is less onerous. And presumably we can expect that the same political levers that are effective in reducing burdensome toil can also be brought to bear to mitigate the environmental damage inflicted by consumption.

We will reach the pessimistic conclusion, on the other hand, if we agree with Cohen about the strong consumption bias of market economies, think that markets are something we just cannot do without, and think that political action to suppress the bias will always be ineffective, at least in the long-term. And if Bowles and Park are right in the paper cited above, if we fail to suppress capitalist inequality, that will shape worker’s desires in consumption (and therefore output) -favouring ways that will make pressure for shorter hours less likely. If we also believe that inter-state competition will lead state policy to favour greater output and that states that refuse to play this game will find themselves outcompeted and undermined by those that do, rather in the manner that English capitalism as depicted in the Manifesto used its cheaper and better goods to force countries stuck in antiquated social forms to transform the way they were organized, then will perhaps think that Max Weber (whose views on rationality and work Cohen rightly castigates) was a better predictor of the future than Marx when he wrote in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism:

This [capitalist] order is now bound to the technical and economic conditions of machine production which today determine the lives of all the individuals who are born into this mechanism, not only those directly concerned with economic acquisition, with irresistible force. Perhaps it will so determine them until the last ton of fossilized coal is burnt. In Baxter’s view the care for external goods should only lie on the shoulders of the “saint like a light cloak, which can be thrown aside at any moment.” But fate decreed that the cloak should become an iron cage.8


  1. The substance of the critique in this chapter also seems to have formed the basis for a TV programme, “Against Capitalism”, which Cohen made for the UK’s Channel Four in 1986 and which, thanks to Nick Vrousalis, is now available on YouTube: part 1 https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=yA9WPQeow9c ; part 2 https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=oD1YEzd6QzQ&t=404s?

  2. See, e.g. John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, part IV (Cambridge: Harvard, 2001).?

  3. It is worth pausing to note that in the forty years since Karl Marx’s Theory of History was published quite a lot of theoretical work has been done both on market socialism and on property-owning democracy. We could recall, for example, John Roemer’s work on market socialism, Martin O’Neill and Thad Williamson’s work on the idea of a property-owning to democracy and Eric Olin Wright’s work on Real UtopiasSee e.g. John Roemer, A Future for Socialism (Harvard, 1994); Martin O’Neill and Thad Williamson, Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond (Wiley, 2012); Erik Olin Wright, Envisioning Real Utopias (Verso, 2010). Perhaps, in the light of that work, Cohen’s scepticism about market-based alternatives to capitalism was unfounded. On the other hand, maybe that skepticism should be bolstered by the way that much of that work seems stuck in extrapolation from a few well-known examples from the past, such as the Mondragon co-operatives and the Lucas Plan, which were already known about and formed the basis for similar speculations in the 1970s. (See Diane Coyle for this observation re Wright: https://crookedtimber.org/2013/03/22/on-erik-olin-wrights-envisioning-real-utopias-diane-coyle/)?

  4. (Cohen’s discussion here has, it must be said, a somewhat dated feel. When I was growing up in 1970s Britain, trade unions were immensely powerful and every schoolchild knew the names of the most important union leaders. Sadly, this is no longer true today. In many ways the same can be said for social democracy. In 1978, the French Parti Socialiste led by Francois Mitterrand was optimistic about willing the legislative elections in alliance with the French Communist Party on a radical programme that included working-time reductions. Today, European social democracy is very much in the doldrums with sharp reductions in its vote share compared to the 1970s. Admittedly, Green parties have arisen in the interim, with commitments to working less and lowering consumption.)?

  5. A brief look at the social science in the area shows that Cohen assertion that things are not much changed since the 1920s is widely contested, but also that there is a lot of argument about what the basic facts are and that different methods of measurement provide wildly different results. So, for example Juliet Schor has claimed that working hours are on the increase, and that US workers put in an extra 163 hours a year in 1990 compared to 1970. Cited in Bluestone, Barry and Rose, Stephen, The Unmeasured Labor Force, the Growth in Work Hours. Levy Economics Institute Public Policy Brief No. 39, Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=103133. Bluestone and Rose in an article which surveys other attempts to measure, found consistent increases in labour supply from those in work, though these seem to follow a longish period of mid-century decline. Samuel Bowles and Yongjin Park report the general trend thus: “in the nations on which data are available, since 1870 work hours have declined substantially, by roughly 50% in continental Europe and by about a third in the English-speaking nations.” Bowles and Park also report a lot of cross-country variation, so, for example: “the work year in Germany exceeded that in the US by 231 hours in 1960, and had fallen to 365 hours less than the US by 1998. Many countries show a decline in hours prior to the early 1980s followed by a levelling off or increase (in Sweden the work year fell by 388 hours over the first two decades and then increased by 128 hours over the next two decades).” (Bowles, Samuel and Park, Yongjin, "Emulation, Inequality, and Work Hours: Was Thorsten Veblen Right?" (2004). Economics Department Working Paper Series. 62. https://doi.org/10.7275/1069200).?

  6. Sarah O’Connor “Workplace exhaustion is a vicious cycle in the UK”, Financial Times, 16 October 2018: https://www.ft.com/content/f959a19c-d095-11e8-a9f2-7574db66bcd5?

  7. Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations. Book V, ch.4, article iv. See also Bowles and Park.?

  8. Max Weber The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (Unwin, 1976) p. 181.?

{ 14 comments }

1

MisterMr 08.28.24 at 1:33 pm

IMHO: the “less labour” result is not all that unlikely, but only in a situation where the government can impose strict limits on all capitalistc firms.

Many of the problems we have now, that resulted from the “neoliberal” phase, happened because the increased level of international trade (and therefore international competition) made it more difficult for governments to push for higer labor standards, because capital can then go in places with lower standards.
This is a very big practical problem because it is unlikely that we will see a peaceful and democratic world government anytime soon, and blocking or limiting international trade has other costs (including the ethical cost of rich countries trying to take away the ladder behind them).

The “keep up with the Joneses” is a very real thing, but it becomes more evident and more necessary as the difference in income widens, which also would probably be reduced by a more social-democratic government.
There are other forms of consumer competition that push towards increased “production”, one example of this is the arms race in education, where the expected level of education one has is always increasing. Other examples are the increase in “bullshit jobs”, like in marketing, where also there is an arms race without a real increase in overall production (but from the point of view of the people working there that is still “production”).

2

wacko 08.28.24 at 1:52 pm

“why states support the bias towards output over leisure”

I don’t think that what states, large companies, and institutions “support” is actually “output”. What they support is “office time”, even though this “office time” is make-believe work, producing no “output” other than rush-hour traffic. And what they oppose is unstructured “free time”.

Why do they, the powers that be (capitalist or not), promote useless “office time”? I don’t know, but I suppose it might have something to do with “social control”. Less free time, more time spent in a structured, hierarchical environment.

3

Chris Bertram 08.28.24 at 2:58 pm

4

Jan Kandiyali 08.28.24 at 10:49 pm

Thanks for the interesting discussion, Chris. One of my favourite chapters of KMTH.

You suggest that discussion of the ills of capitalism in Ch.11 of KMTH are largely absent from Cohen’s later work, which tends to focus on the injustices (exploitation, inequality etc) that come from private ownership of the means of production rather than the way the market stunts human wellbeing. As a general tendency in Cohen’s work, I think that is right. But isn’t this qualified a bit by the discussion of community in Why Not Socialism? The fact that capitalism undermines community is not, I think, for Cohen an injustice but it is a serious defect about it. And it is a defect that flows from the market rather than private property.

I also wonder whether there might be a residual concern with the output bias of capitalism in Cohen’s late defence of conservatism.

Richard Arneson has a sceptical discussion of Cohen’s ‘output bias’ argument in an addendum to a paper on Why Not Socialism, available here:

http://philosophyfaculty.ucsd.edu/faculty/rarneson/documents/writings/why-not-capitalism.pdf

5

Alex SL 08.29.24 at 5:30 am

It doesn’t click for me why markets are unavoidable. One could simply abolish them, and most societies across most of human history didn’t have what we would now recognise as a free market except maybe in very narrow areas and to very limited degrees (like literal farmers’ markets in the town square). The instinct of every market participant is to seek opportunities to undermine the market, establish monopoly or monopsy power, or bribe their way into preferred treatment. Thus most economic activity across history was somewhere between state-run (e.g., Inca empire or ancient Mesopotamia, and in a sense also peasant farming under feudalism, as the feudal lord is effectively the state), state-approved monopolies (e.g., much of early modern age), and guilds that strictly regulated certification and supply to avoid competition (e.g., Medieval times).

Although I am no fan of radical free market ideology myself, I am afraid that this is one of the cases where pointing the finger at capitalism is optimistically narrow. Two alternative angles:

First, as sad as it is, there is something sourly moralistic in many of us that makes people police each other for slacking off and free-loading. That is very understandable as an impulse given where we are coming from: small, tight-knit clans or villages where I may starve or freeze in winter if my brother or neighbour doesn’t help us bring in the harvest or build the shelter. But in a prosperous society where we could all work two days a week and still satisfy all basic needs, that same instinct merely serves to make each other miserable. The result is virtue signalling by participating in superfluous meetings and working unnecessary overtime. Point is, no capitalism or market needed for core human psychology to do its work.

Second, competition between tribes, states, or nations favours short-termism and unsustainable practices. Let’s say there is a nation that uses unsustainable agricultural practices that allow it in the short-term to maintain a large enough population to have an army of 100,000 supplied with the mastersmith armour and siege weapons that only a complex division of labour can provide but who will find all their topsoil eroded in the next 400 years, and another nation that could continue farming for another 20,000 years with its current, sustainable practices but only at the cost of lower productivity and thus lower population density that supports an army of 5,000 supplied with self-made axes and wooden shields. Being overpopulated, the former covets the lands of the latter. What happens? Now both areas are farmed with unsustainable farming practices. Point is, no capitalism or market needed for competition to incentivise short-term gain over long-term benefit.

6

Chris Bertram 08.29.24 at 7:13 am

@Jan – thanks, especially for the link to Arneson. I would respond to Arneson (in part) by pointing to something I mention but neither he nor Cohen does, namely the fact of inter-state competitition and the way this undermines the possibility of the “judicious regulation” he writes about.

@Alex SL Well, even if you think that late-Cohen was wrong about markets, that doesn’t impinge on the argument which is about the tension between early-Cohen beliefs and late-Cohen beliefs.

7

Caleb Althorpe 08.29.24 at 12:43 pm

piggy backing on Jan’s comment about Cohen in Why Not Socialism? arguing market relations undermine community. This no small matter for Cohen given earlier on in WNS he talks about community acting as a constraint on what might be condoned by (egalitarian) justice, suggesting that the value of community might even have priority over the value of justice.

I read Cohen’s comments on markets in WNS less as an embrace but more as a begrudging acknowledgement of the market’s power when it comes to solving the allocation problem. But he doesn’t want to give up hope that one day we might find a justice-(and community-)respecting nonmarket solution to this problem.

8

Peter Dorman 08.29.24 at 4:35 pm

I’m not especially interested in Cohen, but the issue of what I would call income bias (a bias against leisure) has been one I’ve pondered for a long time. I wouldn’t claim to have any clear answers, but:

Bowles and Park are empirically right. In any case, international comparisons are critical to understanding the dynamics of the income bias.
The interests of capitalist firms in expansion are not decisive. (a) Those interests are always negotiated in modern capitalist countries. You have to talk about the interests of other parties too. (b) Firms can substitute more workers for more hours or more effort. This is often against their interest, but not always. Access to a wider range of skills and proclivities can sometimes benefit firms.
The “brainwashing” argument may have some merit, but it is extremely dangerous. There is a history of some people (especially from relatively higher class backgrounds) favoring socialism for largely aesthetic reasons: they don’t like the products or lifestyles that capitalism generates. Well, yeah. But you have to allow for diversity of experience and taste, especially if you care about democracy.
We are witnessing a partial merging of working and nonworking life via working from home and the replacement of actual proximity with virtual. Obviously, this affects only some forms of work, but it’s still a lot. The signoff I am most likely to hear at my (middle class) dog park is “Have to leave and get back to work.” Most people, given the opportunity, really prefer virtual work, but its wider effects on our culture should be examined. (Beyond killing commercial real estate.)

9

Kenny Easwaran 08.29.24 at 8:41 pm

This is really interesting! It seems to me that there might be a different sort of explanation though. Urban planners have talked about a concept they call “Marchetti’s Constant” (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Marchetti%27s_constant), which is the observation that in a large range of societies with different forms of living and transportation, it has been common for people to spend about an hour a day traveling between their home and their place of primary work. I don’t exactly know the empirical backing for this (it does seem to roughly apply in the US, where average commute time is betwee 39 minutes and 72 minutes in all 100 of the largest metro areas: https://www.titlemax.com/discovery-center/100-u-s-cities-ranked-by-commute-time/) or whether it is meant to apply only to town-dwellers, rather than to peasants and other subsistence farmers, or whether there is some way of calculating travel time for them such that it applies as well.

But it may well be that there is some feature of human psychology that leads people to tend to “work” for roughly 8 hours a day over a wide range of economic conditions. It could be something about the way people experience leisure time, such that beyond a certain number of hours in a day, they don’t enjoy it as much as the first few hours, such that not much additional purchasing power for goods is required to tempt people to work a few more hours if they’re currently substantially under 8 hours.

But of course, actual empirical work would be needed to check this, and it’s likely to be very difficult to get an idea of what “work” time is in societies very different from contemporary ones.

10

wetzel-rhymes-with 09.09.24 at 12:10 am

“Why do workers typically push for more consumption rather than for shorter hours?”

Here in Atlanta, water is almost impossible to get out in the city. Everyone buys 24oz sodas because that’s what the city provides. Big Soda Pop hydrates us. Big Soda Pop stocks the grocery store. This is why Kroger’s Big K sodas have no branding and taste awful. Same with Sam’s choice. If Kroger came out with a line of sodas with decent flavors and labels, Coca Cola would crush them.

Who’s over Big Soda Pop? Big Hamburger. If McDonald’s changed from Coke to Pepsi, it would destroy the Coca Cola company. McDonalds doesn’t need the biggest “market cap” to be the most powerful company in the world. McDonalds sits over Big Dairy. If Vermont gets uppity, McDonalds will promote the McDouble, with only one slice of cheese, over the Double Cheeseburger, which is identical in every way except it has two slices of cheese. Likewise, they can punish Big Pork any time they want by withholding the reintroduction of the McRib.

To see the power of Big Hamburger, ask why Kroger or Walmart will never have a griddle to fry a hamburger. The “market” will never provide it. A grocery store in America can make a grilled cheese sandwich or a submarine sandwich, but if it tried to fry hamburgers, I’m certain Big Soda Pop would crush them under direction from Big Hamburger.

11

engels 09.09.24 at 7:43 am

I think in Britain at least it’s not consumerism but the cost of housing (really land) that keeps people on the treadmill.

12

Anna M 09.09.24 at 9:11 am

“Why do workers typically push for more consumption rather than for shorter hours?”

As a guess, I suspect that preferential maintenance of working hours reflects the general increasing transference of surplus value from worker to capitalist class – that is, it is more out of necessity that desire.

I also suspect this relates to my previous points regarding regarding the ongoing attempt to separate social and economic reproduction in order to increase the quantity of indirect (and thus unpaid) productive labour – though perhaps that is an argument for another day.

13

engels 09.09.24 at 12:01 pm

It may be also be worth noting (if my memory is right) that when Cohen was writing “consumption” meant things like electric carving knives (one of his examples iirc) whereas now it means going to university or getting a hip replacement.

14

Kevin A. Carson 09.09.24 at 4:30 pm

The threat of jurisdiction-shopping and relocating production by capitalist firms could be reined in considerably by
1) eliminating intellectual property as a means of enclosing outsourced production within corporate legal walls (allowing Western capital to contract out all their actual production to nominally independent firms while retaining legal monopoly over disposal of the product);
2) eliminating all subsidies to long-distance transportation and shipping, including all the state policies that keep energy inputs artificially abundant and cheap and the U.S. Navy’s role in keeping sea lanes open at taxpayer expense; and
3) eliminating the role of foreign aid and World Bank loans in either subsidizing the offshoring of capital by creating the infrastructural prerequisites of offshored production, or imposing export-oriented development models on Third World states.
These things, coupled with the radical decentralization and ephemeralization of production technology, would likely result in considerable relocalization of production.

Comments on this entry are closed.