The comment thread to my Schmitt post is perking along nicely. (Good poems about taxes, too.) I’m going to take the liberty of elevating some bits of that thread for discussion in this here fresh post. John Quiggin writes:
So, let me start with the observation that war is inherently a negative-sum activity and the empirical fact that, in practice, aggressive war is almost invariably a negative-return activity for the inhabitants of countries that undertake it, Germany in the first half of C20 being a striking example. Schmitt and similar thinkers manage to construct logical frameworks that insulate them from crucial facts like this.
Other commenters eloquently agree. abb1 disagrees:
Thus a war for the most part is not used simply to loot and plunder in the course of it, but it sets the boundaries for looting and plundering during the long period of post-war stability – until the next war. This is a way to avoid a permanent war, permanent negative-sum game – and limited war is an important part of it.
Is not illogical or irrational, it’s a sort of realism.
And yet here is what Schmitt actually says on the subject in The Concept of the Political [amazon – with useful ‘search inside’]:
War as the most extreme political means discloses the possibility which underlies every political idea, namely, the distinction of friend and enemy. This makes sense only as long as this distinction in mankind is actually present or at least potentially possible. On the other hand, it would be senseless to wage war for purely religious, purely moral, purely juristic, or purely economic motives. The friend-and-enemy grouping and therefore also war cannot be derived from these specific antitheses of human endeavor. A war need be neither something religious or something morally good nor something lucrative. War today is in all likelihood none of these. This obvious point is mostly confused by the fact that religious, moral and other antitheses can intensify to political ones and can bring about the decisive friend-or-enemy constellation. If, in fact, this occurs, then the relevant antithesis is no longer purley religious, moral, or economic, but political. The sole remaining question then is always whether such a friend-and-enemy grouping is really at hand, regardless of which human motives are sufficiently strong to have brought it about. (p. 36)
More succinctly:
To demand seriously of human beings that they kill others and be prepared to die themselves so that trade and industry may flourish for the survivors or that the purchasing power of grandchildren may grow is sinister and crazy (p. 48)
Schmitt is running John Quiggin’s point more or less in reverse. Another commenter, Glenn, supports Quiggin in a way that makes this quite clear:
This [what Quiggin wrote], I think, is absolutely crucial. Schmitt is the paradigm case of a thinker caught in a political milieu which retains the possibility of a locally positive-sum war, even when the economic reality no longer allows such an outcome. IIRC, there was a book released in 1910 arguing that European war was no longer possible due to the importance of economic interconnections and the damage war would inflict on them. The havoc wreaked by WWI seems to indicate that it was the exception which (almost) proved the rule. It isn’t that war and conflict is no longer possible under Schmittian terms, but rather that the economic reality no longer insists on the friend-enemy distinction which Schmitt theorizes as fundamental.
But really the argument is more like: since the economic reality does not support war, but it is clear that the possibility of war remains real, therefore the friend-enemy distinction must be fundamental. I have to admit it: that makes a dismal sort of sense to me. And reading the newspaper doesn’t make it make less sense, I’m sad to say. I also agree with Quiggin that Schmitt seems weirdly insulated from these facts, even though he more or less lays them out himself. He complains about one sinister, crazy thing – going to war for profit – but seems placidly untroubled by the sinister craziness of going to war even though its not profitable, just because you are locked in a friend/enemy thing
{ 48 comments }
Adam Kotsko 07.18.06 at 10:54 am
An interesting experiment — read Schmitt alongside Otto’s Idea of the Holy. Just as Otto does with “holiness,” Schmitt tries to set up the political as a purely a priori category. Otto’s use of the term “numinous” to mean “holiness with all impurities from reason, ethics, etc., taken out” is parallel to Schmitt’s insistence on the fundamental friend/enemy distinction abstracted away from all other concerns. Schmitt doesn’t do all the faux-Kantian stuff, but the comparison still seems valid.
Adam Kotsko 07.18.06 at 10:55 am
Crap — now someone is probably going to steal my idea. Another potential line on my CV, thrown out the window because of blogs.
Perhaps blogging is an a priori category, too.
mpowell 07.18.06 at 11:01 am
I don’t know why you’d bother arguing about this negative sum thing. What matters is what will benefit the people actually making the decision and what they actually believe- not what actual cost or benefit the state will receive. Its a lot easier to explain war-making that way.
Steven Poole 07.18.06 at 11:03 am
the economic reality does not support war
Well, before we accept this as true, it’s worth asking: the economic reality for whom? It might bear pointing out that elites != countries, and elites’ interests != their countries’ interests, at least not necessarily. Does KBR weep over the federal deficit?
Scott Martens 07.18.06 at 11:07 am
There’s something wrong with this contention that the friend-enemy distinction is fundamental to war. It’s necessary, in the same way that arms are, but it’s not a fundamental cause.
I think the problem is with Schmitt’s formulation: To demand seriously of human beings that they kill others and be prepared to die themselves so that trade and industry may flourish for the survivors or that the purchasing power of grandchildren may grow is sinister and crazy.
What then does Schmitt think it means to fight for “national greatness”? Yet it is exactly that formulation that has driven plenty of wars. It is not clear to me that Britain or France’s wars of colonial conquest were really driven by any meaningful friend/enemy distinction. “National greatness” was certainly the major motivator for most participants.
No, no politician is so crass as to say “we’re fighting for oil” or something of the sort. But during the first Gulf War, one of the better defenses I heard for it was that it was really all about oil, because oil is life and death for America. Phrasing it as “protecting America’s interests” rather than defending America’s “national greatness” is not much more than a change of terms. I think a lot of people understand the economic reality those phrases stand for.
John Emerson 07.18.06 at 11:07 am
This kind of strict essentialism seems rife in continental thinking, and sometimes analytic philosophy: “Properly speaking, X has nothing whatsoever to do with Y”, which sometimes means only “X and Y are not exactly the same; some Xes are not Y, and some Ys are not X”: whereas there might be a very strong “family resemblance”, statistical overlap, or historical relationship between X and Y .
“Properly” in this phrase seems to mean “speaking appropriately and rightly” but really means “defining these terms as narrowly as possible”.
So I think that Schmitt’s first mistake, one to which philosophical types are terribly successful, was to look for an essence in the first place. But the particular essence he chose seems to show a bias toward conflict and violence on his part.
I haven’t read Otto, but what Kotsko said seems right. You might even be able to make a collection of definitions of this kind.
abb1 07.18.06 at 11:12 am
the economic reality for whom?
Yes, elites, of course. But sometimes also everyone else. It would be hard to argue, I think, that the WWII wasn’t benefitial to virtually everyone in the US (except for those who died). Compare 1930s and 1950s.
Steven Poole 07.18.06 at 11:19 am
Sure, abb1, sometimes. I was just pointing out that the occasions when everyone else doesn’t benefit are no proof that no one has, no proof that a war has made no “economic sense” to anybody.
Jim Harrison 07.18.06 at 11:20 am
As I recall, Hegel maintained that the state rises above the mere selfishness and calculation of civil society precisely because in war, the state’s characteristic activity, people have to choose an ideal over their own lives. Absent the edifying language, this notion isn’t without merit. After all, it does seem that war and the possibility of war were crucial to the development of organized states in Mesopotamia and elsewhere. Absent war, it’s pretty hard to understand how ruling groups and leaders could have managed the level of exploitation and control that goes with civilization. Why else put up with Sargon? Heck, why else put up with Cheney?
abb1 07.18.06 at 11:32 am
Steven, you’re right of course, nevertheless pointing to the elite as the sole perpetrator is somewhat misleading, I think. They do usually try to share the loot, promise every soldier an estate in Ukraine or something like that. I wonder what the US opinion polls on Iraq would look like now if gasoline was sold today for 20 cents/gallon.
Adam Kotsko 07.18.06 at 11:32 am
I think the strict essentialism has to do with concepts either whose hold on people seems to be waning or whose definitions seem to be radically changing in a short amount of time. I’m seeing this a lot in my theology reading — people care less about faith, and so Tillich (or anyone else) comes along and says, “The problem is that people misunderstand what faith means. In reality, it essentially means [insert entirely novel definition of faith here].” The attempt at descriptivism in analytic philosophy might help them avoid this kind of thing more often than the continentals do — although I would argue that what you’re describing as a “continental” tendancy is just a general philosophical tendancy, maybe a “Platonic” as opposed to “Aristotelian” tendancy.
Steven Poole 07.18.06 at 11:34 am
The same argument is made, less loftily but perhaps more entertainingly, in the Jet Li film Hero. For me, the brilliance of the kung-fu makes a good pill-sweetener.
Vance Maverick 07.18.06 at 11:39 am
Scott, I think fighting for “national greatness” is sinister and crazy. Fighting for the country (to keep it free, etc.) is another story.
Perhaps you didn’t intend to distinguish these?
Steven Poole 07.18.06 at 11:43 am
pointing to the elite as the sole perpetrator is somewhat misleading
Not what I was saying, though; merely pointing out the trivial general fact that elite interests do not necessarily coincide with the country’s interest at large.
I wonder what the US opinion polls on Iraq would look like now if gasoline was sold today for 20 cents/gallon.
Greg Palast has a theory about all that. According to him, there were two factions in the administration planning – the “pure” neocons, who wanted to use cheap Iraqi oil to destroy OPEC, and those aligned with oil interests, who wanted to make sure Iraqi oil was not developed so as to keep prices high. Interesting if true.
Matt Kuzma 07.18.06 at 11:45 am
since the economic reality does not support war, but it is clear that the possibility of war remains real, therefore the friend-enemy distinction must be fundamental.
This argument is supported by a little cross-disciplinary action: the us-versus-them mindset is well documented in psychology. People will generate us-versus-them dichotomies out of next to nothing. In one experiment, subjects were assigned one of two colors randomly, and given a shirt of that color. Over time, the subjects began to view members of the other group unfavorably and actively discouraged their fellow subjects from associating with members of the other group.
It is actually part of our nature to view outsiders with disdain and suspicion, and to, under extreme circumstances, cease to consider them human. Fortunately, it’s also part of our nature to recognize our instincs and act against them.
Glenn Bridgman 07.18.06 at 11:53 am
The point I was trying to make was slightly more subtle than the one I actually did make.
Insofar as it makes sense to discuss of the “friend-enemy” distinction as a priori and fundamental, economic motives will be the reason. You are plopped down in some country and for various ahistorical reasons it will make sense to go to invade your neighbors and come back with some nice loot. Thus, certain people/countries will be your enemies merely by virtue of being where they are and having what they have.
This isn’t necessarily the only reason someone will be your enemy–just that the other enemies will be your enemies for reasons contingent on your specific historical relationship with those people. Most notably, you could be pissed about the last time they came over and took your stuff, regardless of whether it makes economic sense to go try to get your stuff back—Alsace-Lorraine, anyone?
If you look at wars in the modern era, I believe they mostly support this interpretation. Either they take place in area’s where the modern economic system hasn’t integrated sufficiently yet and the “invade-and-loot” method still makes sense (thinking mostly of Africa/ME here) or the wars have pretty direct lineages to prior wars (thinking mainly of all the wars caused by decolonization etc.) There are a few wars that don’t fit this mold, mainly the proxy wars in the shadow of the Cold War, and I am uncertain as to there classification, although I suspect they are somewhat of a combination of the above.
Essentially I think Schmitt is conflating two different understandings of “enemy”. The first is where people are enemies merely because they are–cue the crime lord telling his victim that it is “only business.” The second is where people are enemies because they truly hate the other person. Only the former is really fundamental in the way Schmitt wants it to be and it is also the type which has mostly had its legs cut out from under it by the modern economic system. The latter can still cause wars, but it is also not a fundamental property, as it depends on all sorts of historical peculiarities as a yet more fundamental cause.
Lastly, I am wary about explaining wars in terms of the interests of the “elites,” especially in democracies. This isn’t to say that it isn’t accurate, but rather that it sounds dangerously close to some Marxian conception of “false consciousness.” This carries with it all the usual problems, not the least of which is that it is very often a self-sealer.
Jon H 07.18.06 at 11:54 am
Wikipedia (FWIW) says of Schmitt “it must be remembered that, along with the early Heidegger, Schmitt lent his considerable authority to the Nazi regime, and played a leading role in constructing the legal façade that justified its seizure of power.”
So that would make David Addington the Bush Administration’s Carl Schmitt, no?
mcd 07.18.06 at 11:57 am
The friend-enemy (or opponent) distinction is not the most basic or fundemental concept, since it simply leaves unexplained what interests lead actors to sort other actors as friend or foe.
abb1 07.18.06 at 11:59 am
…the “pure†neocons, who wanted to use cheap Iraqi oil to destroy OPEC, and those aligned with oil interests, who wanted to make sure Iraqi oil was not developed so as to keep prices high.
Obviously the second fraction won (not surprisingly), because Iraq re-joined OPEC almost immediately after the US occupation. Here’s Michael Kinsley protesting: Ten billion reasons why Iraq shouldn’t rejoin OPEC. Not that it made much difference – considering the level of oil production there, but clearly they thought it might.
Scott Martens 07.18.06 at 12:00 pm
Vance, the point was that Schmitt is claiming that it would be senseless to fight for economic reasons, and therefore that the pre-existence of a friend-enemy distinction has to explain modern warfare. I think that it’s nuts to assume that wars are generally conducted for rational reasons, but I also think that people are also prepared to fight wars for economic causes when given only the very thinnest of fig leaves for doing so.
I think wars for “national greatness” are such transparent nonsense that it only makes sense to evoke it when all the participants really believe some more mundane reason exists that, for some reason, can’t be publicly stated.
Adam Kotsko 07.18.06 at 12:16 pm
McD, Why can’t it just be a fundamental interest in dividing up other actors (or groups) into friends and foes?
Steven Poole 07.18.06 at 12:18 pm
Lastly, I am wary about explaining wars in terms of the interests of the “elites,†especially in democracies […] it sounds dangerously close to some Marxian conception of “false consciousness.â€
Sorry, I meant no such offence by “elites”. Please replace it with any other similiar word. But why “especially in democracies”?
Glenn Bridgman 07.18.06 at 12:41 pm
Mea culpa, I was using democracy as a proxy for other things that make that explanation implausible, but you’re right, there is nothing about democracy as such which make that accurate.
Jim Harrison 07.18.06 at 1:44 pm
Wars obviously benefit particular groups of people such as military entrepreneurs in the short term, but the war system, broadly speaking, is crucial to the maintenance of the privileges and power of any group that controls the state. Note this is not a Marxist conclusion. The state holders aren’t always or even usually a class.
abb1 07.18.06 at 1:54 pm
Why is it necessarily critical to the maintenance of the privileges and power of any group that controls the state?
Jim Harrison 07.18.06 at 2:39 pm
In a pinch, a government can seek legitimacy by providing benefits to its citizens; but, as I read history, war and the threat of war are the more usual ways that the few have most often convinced the many to freely surrender their liberties, their property, and sometimes their lives. War benefits the state and the interests tied to the state–think of the aggrandizement of state power in Europe that went along with the military revolution of the 16th and 17th Centuries and the dimunition of state power that went along with the pacification of Western Europe in the postwar period.
It’s not for nothing that there haven’t been a heck of a lot of peaceful authoritarians.
abb1 07.18.06 at 3:07 pm
I don’t know, the WWI seemed to cause a lot of the groups that controled various states to lose their control forever. When the population is armed and unhappy, that’s not good for the elite.
Jim Harrison 07.18.06 at 3:32 pm
The ideal situation for a ruling group is to maintain a system of limited wars that help enforce social hierarchy. People like Frederick the Great and Bismark understood this proviso perfectly. So did military theorists like Baron Jomini who belonged to what amounted to an international military caste. He was terrified of popular war.
The administration also seems to understand that a real, balls-out conflict with a serious enemy would be too much of a good thing. The French demographer Todd has pointed out that the administration’s military adventures have been targetted to contemptably weak targets. Nobody’s going to rile up China or Russia. The War on Terror, aka WWIII or WWIV, is ideal: it has greatly augmented the power of the central government, provided huge winfall profits to Republican clients, but–we hope–will remain small potatoes. Unfortunately, miscalculations are perfectly possible and perhaps likely, especially since the right tends to make some pretty optimistic assumptions about America’s continuing economic and military strength. One of these days they may pick on the wrong enemy.
MattXIV 07.18.06 at 3:42 pm
I think the discussion of “elites” and their motivations for war is a red herring with regards to Schmitt’s point, which seems to focus more on how popular support (the people who must actually “kill others and be prepared to die themselves”) for war is obtained. Honest or not, some convincing rationale has to be offered up to the public independent of the motivations of those in power. Schmitt seems to be saying that moral, economic, and religious goals are insufficient motives for war on their own and need to be combined with the recognition of a friend-enemy distinction in order for war to make sense to the people fighting it. Friend-enemy distinctions must exist independent of economic/moral/religous motivations, since if you take into account those motivations, war still doesn’t seem justified without the friend-enemy distinction.
Steven Poole 07.18.06 at 4:08 pm
I think the discussion of “elites†and their motivations for war is a red herring […] Honest or not, some convincing rationale has to be offered up to the public independent of the motivations of those in power.
Well, and by whom is the rationale offered up?
By the way isn’t Schmitt saying, not that the friend/enemy distinction is somehow a fundamental underlying truth, but rather that it’s the magic propagandistic juice that, supervening on existing “antitheses”, gives them real political “energy”?
MattXIV 07.18.06 at 5:21 pm
Re 30:
I think Schmitt’s point is that it doesn’t really matter who offers the rationale, or what the rationale is (popular sentiment can force the hand of those in power just as easily as elites can manipulate the public), it won’t provide the political energy unless it taps into a friend-enemy divide.
I get the impression that Schmitt is saying the reverse – that the application of complementary “antitheses†to an existing divide creates the political energy by deepening and sharpening it, allowing people to be pursuaded to do things that would seem insane in its absence.
OTOH, I’m no expert on Schmitt, so I may be wrong.
John Quiggin 07.18.06 at 5:35 pm
All of this gets the core of my problem with Schmitt, or more precisely the way Schmitt is treated nowadays. If you want an elegantly written encapsulation of the “sinister and crazy” thinking that gives us wars, Schmitt is your man, just as Lenin is the ideal exemplar for anyone wanting to summarise the thinking behind unconstrained power politics. Their usefulness for these purposes is enhanced by their association with the most disastrous failures of such ideas.
But people seem to want to view Schmitt as theorist about this kind of thinking, with whom it is useful to engage, rather than as an example of it, and therefore an appropriate object of study.
Jim Harrison 07.18.06 at 6:31 pm
Schmitt reluctantly concluded that he lived in a democratic age. His problem was how to maintain a decent, hierarchical society despite the fact that the population couldn’t just be ignored in a time of mass conscription armies. Since mass conscription armies are an anachronism now, I assume that a resurrected Schmitt would have to change his tune a bit. “Democracy” has been a rather meaningless word for quite a while now.
I agree with John Quiggin that Schmitt is or ought to be considered a pathological character. What bothers me is that his kind of thinking has struck a chord, not only with rightists, but with people who are officially supposed to be liberals. Indeed, most of the themes of early 20th Century fascism and extreme authoritarianism have resurfaced in this last couple of decades, though I’m not sure whether the Neocons and liberal hawks recognize that their integral nationalism, voluntarism, and the cult of the Enemy put ’em in pretty bad company. The point here, however, isn’t to call anybody bad names. Indeed, political correctness has made it impossible to admit that, as a matter of fact, fascism or at any event its ideological matrix is very appealing to intellectuals.
Anderson 07.18.06 at 7:56 pm
Hm, this thread motivated me to pick up my copy of Political Theology and read it (pamphlet-sized work that it is).
If you define “sovereignty” in a manner that precludes anything but an authoritarian sovereign personality, then it is not too surprising that you conclude that only such an entity can exercise sovereignty.
The guy was certainly smart, but put me down with the Lenin-comparison comment above, until I read something else of Schmitt’s.
mcd 07.18.06 at 10:49 pm
#21: Because it doesn’t say anything except that people do things because they do things. And also, dividing people into friends and foes is much more intense (and non-obvious) than the recognition of friends and strangers, ot acquaintances and kin. One would like some reason to account for the extra “effort” involved in making the dichotomy.
Steven Poole 07.19.06 at 2:41 am
If you want an elegantly written encapsulation of the “sinister and crazy†thinking that gives us wars, Schmitt is your man
Well, I think he’s a bad writer, but the following doesn’t strike me as particularly sinister or crazy (from before and after John Holbo’s second quote):
I can’t find Schmitt to be “placidly untroubled”, in John’s phrase, by war here. Obviously there are arguments to be had about what constitutes an “existential threat”, and Schmitt might have a sinister notion about that somewhere else, which wouldn’t surprise me given his history. But this particular text isn’t very ambivalent about the desirability of war in general.
John Quiggin 07.19.06 at 3:38 am
Brad DeLong has suitably bloodthirsty quotes, and there’s more good discussion in the comments thread.
I read the quotes John H has given as disdaining rational arguments for war precisely to promote irrational hatred as the appropriate basis (I think that’s John’s reading also).
Steven Poole 07.19.06 at 4:01 am
JQ – I still can’t see where any of John H’s or my quotes necessarily promote irrational hatred: what I just cited appears to say clearly that war, though it often arises through irrational hatred, is only justified in the presence of a real “existential threat” (defined howsoever).
I guess one’s reading hangs on whether one thinks of Schmitt as being descriptive (lamentably, although there are rarely good reasons for war, unjustified wars happen anyway because irrational hatred is stoked up) or normative (irrational hatred is a good reason for war). On the surface, the passages here cited seem to me to be saying the former. I don’t see a good textual reason to read them otherwise. I would hesitate to decide my interpretation on some such basis as “He was a fascist, so he must have meant the latter.” (Not that I am accusing you of doing so.)
But perhaps the problem is that his prose does not really distinguish clearly between descriptive and normative modes. He may even, of course, be obscuring the difference deliberately, encoding a hidden message for initiates à la Strauss.
abb1 07.19.06 at 5:34 am
It’s not clear what he is talking about at all:
What does the word ‘political’ mean to this guy? I suspect he may be using ‘political’ as synonym of ‘nationalistic’ or something.
John Quiggin 07.19.06 at 5:39 am
I must admit, I don’t see the problem with saying “He was a fascist, so he must have meant the latter.â€, at least if you substitute “Nazi” for “fascist”. It’s absurd to postulate an anti-war Nazi, so only the pro-war reading is left.
So, the “existential threat” language could be read to mean that only purely defensive war is permissible, but if Schmitt had meant that he would have ended up in Buchenwald or exile. Alternatively, it could mean something like a maximal Lebensraum doctrine – the existence of the Aryan race is incompatible with anything less than absolute power in Europe. My money is on this interpretation.
I guess the hidden message interpretation is also possible, but then which is the esoteric and which the exoteric?
This links to the more general problem of whether a philosopher’s views can/should be linked to their political actions. Heidegger is the obvious problem case – I’ve been thinking about a post on this.
abb1 07.19.06 at 5:46 am
I think maybe what he’s saying here is that it’s crazy to expect people to fight and die for any rational reason, so the only way to convince them to go fight and die is to give them an irrational one – chauvinistic (or ‘political’ as he calls it).
So, if this is correct, then this is more about propaganda than anything else; which is not necessarily all that interesting. This is all quite trivial these days.
Steven Poole 07.19.06 at 6:18 am
I guess the hidden message interpretation is also possible, but then which is the esoteric and which the exoteric?
I guess that my or abb1’s surface readings would be the exoteric, and yours – on your very plausible interpretation of what he actually means by “existential threat” – would be the esoteric. But it is awfully turgid stuff in any case.
Steven Poole 07.19.06 at 6:20 am
What does the word ‘political’ mean to this guy?
I read this essay as defining “political” to mean partaking of a friend/enemy distinction, whether fictive or real.
Steven Poole 07.19.06 at 6:37 am
By the way, I don’t know his other work enough to judge whether it might also be possible that Schmitt was one of those who supported the Nazi party in 1932 (when this was written) without assuming that a world war would be part of the package, and changed his mind to become explicitly pro-war later? If so, that would not retroactively invert the apparent meaning of this text.
abb1 07.19.06 at 6:49 am
He says:
so, I think ‘political’ just means ‘nationalistic’.
Stalinists divided people to ‘socially allied’, ‘socailly allien’ and ‘enemies of the people’. A typical criminal, murderer for example, whose parents were factory workers would count as ‘socially allied’. A radical marxist professor would forever remain ‘socailly allien’.
The fascist approach seems similar, only it’s based on nation instead of class.
Anderson 07.19.06 at 9:11 am
“Brad DeLong has suitably bloodthirsty quotes”
One of those is from Genghis Khan, not Schmitt, though DeLong suggests they’re soulmates.
sara 07.19.06 at 9:01 pm
War for profit has been viewed negatively in the Western tradition unless it can be recast as what Vollmann terms “defense of ground,” namely colonial possessions or allied communities. Only when capitalism became dominant, warfare to protect mercantile interests became acceptable.
I’m not surprised that Schmitt continues this idea.
Whether William Vollmann should be considered an authority is debatable, but his typology of justifications for violence is interesting. I have skimmed (could not bring myself to buy) the unabridged edition of Rising Up.
gr 07.20.06 at 3:26 pm
I just read Martin Van Creveld, ‘The Transformation of War’. It contains a chapter ‘What War is Fought For’ that struck me as a plausible interpretation of Schmitt’s view (Van Creveld doesn’t explicitly cite Schmitt, but he appears in the bibliography), while being much more accessible than Schmitt himself. Worth checking out in this context.
Comments on this entry are closed.