Non sequitur

by John Q on January 8, 2007

In comments on an open thread on my blog, Michael Greinecker points to a truly strange response to arguments for a zero rate of social time preference.

Crucial quote

I found myself becoming very curious whether economists who support Sir Nicholas’s social discount rate of zero, such as econ bloggers John Quiggin and Brad DeLong, identify themselves as pro-choice or pro-life, and whether they had considered the Stern Report from this angle.

My response has been anticipated by a commenter who observes

Strange as it may seem to Economist writers, there are phenomena in the world that aren’t particularly illuminated by applying economic concepts. Attitudes towards abortion have nothing at all to do with discounting rates.

Others in the comments thread spell this out.

One odd feature of the Economist blog is that contributions are anonymous. I know that Megan McArdle (aka Jane Galt) has something to do with the site, but I have no idea whether she wrote this piece. While I’m used to pseudonymous commenters, most economics bloggers are (as Matt Yglesias puts it) proudly eponymous, or at least easily identified, and I find this a more satisfactory mode for arguing about issues like the Stern Review, though can’t exactly say why.

{ 45 comments }

1

uiop 01.08.07 at 9:05 pm

I suspect you mean for the last word to be “why,” rather than “way.”

2

Francis 01.08.07 at 9:31 pm

There is, at the time of this comment, a 60-comment thread on this issue over at Marginal Revolution. Ms. Galt makes an appearance.

3

John Emerson 01.08.07 at 10:46 pm

For me degrading the world so that no future generations can ever be born is not the same thing as aborting an equivalent number of individual human fetusses and preventing them from being born. And diminishing the world of future actual people is not the same as preventing other potential people from becoming actual. I don’t think that environmental ethics is grounded on relationships of obligation between a present group of individuals and not-yet extant groups of future individuals.

I also don’t think that the obligations of present day individuals toward the future need to be expressed in terms of obligations of an overlapping series of contemporaries into the future (me to my younger contemporaries and they to their younger contemporaries whom I will never know). There’s nothing terribly wrong with that but I don’t think it’s right to insist on it. I don’t have an obligation to some particular group of unborn fetuses even though I do have an abligation to the future human race as a whole.

I think questions of totalization are very important; we’re not talking about some specific group, but of all humans indefinitely into the future, the very possibility of continued humanity. The difference between killing a certain number of animals (individual victims) as opposed to exterminating a species, or of confining the whole species to an impoverished and hostile habitat.

So I’d just translate it into three basic primitives or axioms:

1. One of the worst of possible crimes would be to permanently diminish, impoverish, or destroy the whole human race.

2. This principle is to be regarded as more certain than any metaethical justification we can build under it.

3. #1 is true even though it does not necessarily tell you exactly how to satisfy it; that is, it’s a criterion for results that doesn’t include much help on methods and specifics.

The present discussion would be fitted under dealing with the consequences of #3. But I don’t see how the zero-discount discounting framework (which sounds to me like zero-cabbage cabbage soup) helps much.

4

Brad DeLong 01.08.07 at 10:58 pm

Yes, I have. The utilitarian arguments that would make you pro-life also make you think that as many pregnancies as possible should be mandatory for all women…

It’s not an issue that utilitarianism handles well at all.

5

Brock 01.09.07 at 12:13 am

The mandate of utilitarianism toward population growth greatly depends on whether the nigh-inevitable extinction of humanity will be hastened by increased population or not.

If increased population means that we will run out of resources, or choke on our own waste, then utilitarianism demands zero population growth, once we get beyond some sustainable number.

But if there’s no such danger, then utilitarianism mandates increased population, to maximize total utility before everyone is killed by a huge meteor strike, or the eventual heat-death of the sun.

It’s a very big unknown: big enough for me to square my utilitarian philosophy with my pro-choice politics, at least until I have more information.

6

Daniel 01.09.07 at 1:22 am

Whoever wrote that comment also *still* hasn’t managed to get the distinction right between a zero discount rate and a zero rate of pure time preference.

7

sd 01.09.07 at 1:28 am

John Emerson wrote:

“And diminishing the world of future actual people is not the same as preventing other potential people from becoming actual.”

But this is precisely the inconsistency that the Economist blogger is concerned with. Because there are no “future actual people” in any sense that is distinguishable from the “future actual fetuses delivered to term” that would exist if abortion were banned. Barring the odd centegenarian that has just been born, the people of the 100 year out future aren’t actual at all – they are potential. And, as the blogger points out, a helluva a lot further from being realized potential than the fetus in the womb today.

Think of it this way. In the year 2106 there will be 100 river delta dwelling Bangladeshis if we put no more carbon into the air, and 80 if we do put more carbon in the air. Let us stipulate that all else being equal, we would indeed love to put more carbon in the air.

In the year 2007 there will be 100 babies born if abortion were illegal, but only 80 if abortion were legal. Let us stipulate that 20 pregnant women would prefer not to deliver their fetuses to term.

If we have an obligation to interfere in the exercise of the basic liberty of drivers today because of the interests of the 20 Bangladeshis who would not be born if we continue to allow unfettered carbon emissions, then it at least raises the question of why we don’t have an obligation to interfere in the exercise of the basic liberty of women because of the interests of the 20 babies who would not be born if we allow abortion.

Reducing carbon emissions today has costs. Real costs that will cause pain and suffering for real people who are alive today. The Stern report implies that this is right and good because if we do not reduce emissions we will impose costs on potential people who are not yet alive. And those future people (and their interests) are worth just as much as current people (and their interests). Fair enough.

But banning abortion would result in the birth of more babies. These babies will generally be born into tough circumstances, but the lack of massive suicide on the part of the poor and disadvantaged is a pretty good clue to the fact that people living in tough circumstances prefer to do so than not to live at all. So why would we not impose costs – real costs that will cause pain and suffering for pregnent women today – in order to provide on balance a greater benefit to those babies.

8

John Emerson 01.09.07 at 1:56 am

Well, as I’ve said, I don’t think this is about a relationship between one group of individuals (the present generation) and a second group of individuals (some future generation). It’s about the present generation and the human species as a whole or the possibilities of human life as a whole. The worst possibility is not that some group of individuals will be harmed, but but that something would diminish the human race, or humanity as a whole, or human possibility in general. That’s the context I propose.

From this point of view, I’m reluctant to argue environmental ethics primarily in terms of the present human generation’s utility at all, granted theat politically we will have to persuade the present human generation.

So I want to get away from the overlapping generations way of reaching future generations, and just define an obligation independent of contemporary individual situations and reltionships. This requires giving some kind of status to not-yet-real future humans, as bearers of human possibility, but does not require giving status to every fetus or every potential human as long as human possibility is being maintained.

As far as the argument that the greatest good of the greatest number means the more people the better, if you start trying to make a utilitarian out of me I’ll just decide that it’s a lot more economical to maximize aggregate pleasure by jerking off millions of lab rats than it would be to do so by raising as many humans as possible to a non-negative level of happiness. With humans there’s just too much risk of maximizing anhedonia and misery rather than pleasure.

9

uiop 01.09.07 at 4:02 am

sd: You seem to have made a bizarre argument even more bizarre. Please clarify if I have completely missed your point.

Perhaps you made a poor generalization from an odd example and will slap yourself in the morning when you read what you wrote. But interpreting what you wrote literally, you think that defenders of the Stern Report tacitly believe that there is a completely invariant GDP per capita. Thus, we ought to mitigate the widespread damage that global warming will cause because, although GDP per capita will remain constant, in a world in which global warming has been mitigated there will be *more people* than otherwise.

Does anyone believe this? That the goal of the Kyoto Protocol, etc., is to increase the human population in the year 2100? I suspect that you don’t really think this, because that would be distinctly odd.

My next guess would be that you have been lured into an equivocation by multiple possible uses of the word “potential.” There is one sense in which we look at an acorn and say “that acorn is potentially an oak.” We are making a statement about what we understand to be a physical possibility for a particular entity. An orange is potentially an orange tree; it is also potentially my breakfast; it is also potentally a mouldy orange. There is also a sense in which we can look at a young oak forest and say “Today, there are only 100 oak trees here, but ecology tells us that in 200 years there will be 1000 oak trees. The 900 trees that aren’t here now will actually exist one day, but right now they only exist potentially.”

I am pretty sure this confusion is the only way you could get from “caring, at least somewhat, about people who will be alive in a century” to “caring, at least somewhat, about blastocysts.”

Have you made this mistake? Have you confused the sense in which an acorn is “potentially” an oak tree with the sense in which each oak tree which will actually exist in 200 years is “only potential” now? If you made this sort of equivocation, you could make an argument like this: “You think that we shouldn’t wantonly do things that will kill this oak forest in a century? But this must mean that you care about potential oak trees, since most of the trees that will exist then don’t exist now. But if you care about ‘potential oak trees,’ why don’t you kill all the squirrels to stop them from eating acorns, huh? Acorns are potential oak trees too!” If you don’t understand what’s wrong with this argument, sd, re-read.

For the purposes of the illustrative bad argument in the preceding paragraph, please ignore the fact that squirrels are part of the oak life cycle.

10

conchis 01.09.07 at 7:39 am

“It’s not an issue that utilitarianism handles well at all.”

Brad, I think this is true mainly to the extent that you equate utilitarianism with it’s classical total-utility or average-utility versions. There are other options that are rather better at handling such matters. Check out the work of Blackoby, Bossert and Donaldson on critical-level utilitarian principles, for example. That said, I do this that this is an area that consequentialists of all stripes should be more concerned about than they appear to be.

11

sd 01.09.07 at 8:38 am

uiop wrote:

“I am pretty sure this confusion is the only way you could get from “caring, at least somewhat, about people who will be alive in a century” to “caring, at least somewhat, about blastocysts.””

And I’m pretty sure that I’m not the one confused here. One needn’t care about a blastocyst per se. One can simply observe that if public policy protects blastocysts from harm there will be more people born, and that these people have rights and interests which we should take into account under a moral and analytical scheme in which we take into account the rights and interests of people who will be alive in 2106 – to the extent that our public policies today impact those rights and interests.

Your point about total population vs. average GDP per capita is fine. I was merely setting up a hypothetical to illustrate that the Economist blogger was not batty – that any concern for far-future human beings who will exist 100 years from now seems a little odd if we don’t have equal or greater concern for near-future human beings who will exist 7 months from now. The latter after all being much closer to realized potential than the former.

12

Matt McIrvin 01.09.07 at 9:19 am

But banning abortion would result in the birth of more babies. These babies will generally be born into tough circumstances, but the lack of massive suicide on the part of the poor and disadvantaged is a pretty good clue to the fact that people living in tough circumstances prefer to do so than not to live at all. So why would we not impose costs – real costs that will cause pain and suffering for pregnent women today – in order to provide on balance a greater benefit to those babies.

Actually, this is an argument that anti-abortion and even moderately pro-abortion people seem to easily slip into, when discussing such ethically tricky things as genetic selection of embryos–the idea that it’s wrong to prevent someone from living on the basis of a disability that would not prevent the eventual person from wishing he or she had not lived.

It has an appeal, but the thing that bothers me about this argument is pretty much as you say: if you apply it to family size, it means that everyone should keep pumping out kids until the resulting misery is so great that the next one would prefer not to have been born. Which at least seems wrong.

13

Brock 01.09.07 at 11:52 am

If we have an obligation to interfere in the exercise of the basic liberty of drivers today because of the interests of the 20 Bangladeshis who would not be born if we continue to allow unfettered carbon emissions, then it at least raises the question of why we don’t have an obligation to interfere in the exercise of the basic liberty of women because of the interests of the 20 babies who would not be born if we allow abortion.

But it’s not the interests of the 20 never-existing Bangladeshis that we’re worried about so much. It’s all the other not-yet-existing-but-will-be-someday and currently-existing-and-will-still-be-then Bangladeshis who are going to end up as refugees when their country floods.

14

Bernard Yomtov 01.09.07 at 11:53 am

The Economist leaps from the right of a woman to have an abortion to the conclusion that no one else has any obligations with respect to fetuses.

This is wrong. No one thinks the fetus is worthless. What pro-choice advocates believe is that the rights of the pregnant woman outweigh those of the fetus, to varying degrees. They do not believe that society has no obligation to protect fetuses in the huge majority of cases where the woman wishes to give birth.

15

Alison 01.09.07 at 12:44 pm

Bangladeshis who would not be born if we continue to allow unfettered carbon emissions

Agree with what was said by brock, bernard etc.

And in any case, it’s not a philosophical problem of reducing the numbers of people ‘who would not be born’ – in any future there are infinite numbers of people who will not be born – it’s about avoiding a future where people die in pain and misery. And it’s ultimately about avoiding our species dying out altogether.

16

Alex Gregory 01.09.07 at 2:14 pm

No 14: “No one thinks the fetus is worthless.”

You’re correct that the inference in the economist is invalid, but the above is incorrect. Whilst many “pro-choice” people might support some fetal rights but more for the mother-to-be, others think that the fetus has no rights at all (which isn’t the same as saying that a newly born baby can’t complain if it was harmed, say through smoking, back when it was in the womb).

The wikipedia article contains some information on this.

17

Kenny Easwaran 01.09.07 at 3:08 pm

No rights doesn’t equal worthless. My computer has no rights, but it’s definitely not worthless!

And Peter Singer’s utilitarianism seems to deal with many of these questions in a relatively intuitive way. (Though many people disagree with his thoughts about disabilities.) Basically, it’s unclear whether never having existed (as a conscious person) at all is actually a harm to anyone. Early enough abortion just prevents a person from ever having existed as a person. Global warming may well either kill conscious people, or make their ordinary lives harder.

18

uiop 01.09.07 at 3:43 pm

sd- Take this phrase, written by you: “any concern for far-future human beings who will exist 100 years from now seems a little odd if we don’t have equal or greater concern for near-future human beings who will exist 7 months from now.”

There will be six billion human beings, give or take, existing seven months from now. We have no reason to have more or less concern for those people, relative to the billions of human beings who will exist seven years from now, or seventy years from now. I see no connection to abortion.

But this isn’t what you mean, is it? When you say “equal or greater concern for… human beings who will exist 7 months from now,” you must mean “equal or greater concern for… fetuses.” Unless you mean that, there is no connection to abortion. If you do mean that, you have made a mistake. There is nothing odd about caring about the people who will existing is 2107AD, and not caring about blastocysts. I suspect your error is related to an equivocation over the word “potential.”

19

Bernard Yomtov 01.09.07 at 4:58 pm

My computer has no rights,

Come the revolution, you’ll talk different.

20

Paul 01.09.07 at 5:56 pm

“Strange as it may seem to Economist writers, there are phenomena in the world that aren’t particularly illuminated by applying economic concepts. Attitudes towards abortion have nothing at all to do with discounting rates.”
This, without more, is a pretty substandard response, and the follow up “and who are you anyway, I like to argue about people, not ideas” doesn’t help much.
While the posited relationship between discount rates and abortion is by no means conclusive, I think there’s at least a prima facie case to be answered when you state that you value the utility of future potential humans equally with your own, but the utility of a specific potential human not at all. I think some of the above responses do a decent job of resolving the apparent contradiction, but “it’s not a question for economics, you fool” does not.

21

Daniel 01.09.07 at 7:57 pm

Paul, it’s not a substandard response at all. The point is that the question of abortion has nothing to do with discount rates. Adopting a different social rate of pure time preference isn’t going to give you a different answer to the question of whether abortion is morally justifiable or not.

22

Daniel 01.09.07 at 8:00 pm

One can simply observe that if public policy protects blastocysts from harm there will be more people born

One cannot observe any such thing, least of all “simply”.

23

Paul 01.09.07 at 8:56 pm

Daniel,
A very high rate of time preference is consistent with placing a low value on the future wellbeing of potential humans not presently in existence and visa versa. The value we place on the future wellbeing of humans not presently in existence is one of the questions that ought to influence our position on abortion. It may not be determinative, because we may decide on the basis of the mother’s right to bodily autonomy for instance, but it’s certainly part of the conversation.

There are a few dozen posts scattered across various threads, including this one, engaging with that relationship, which provides further evidence that it does, in fact, exist. JQ’s post tries to sidestep that question, and as such isn’t a sufficient response, and certainly doesn’t justify the snarky tone he choses to adopt.

24

engels 01.09.07 at 10:15 pm

Paul – You seem to be using the phrase “potential human being” to talk about two rather different things.

In the context of Stern, the “potential human beings” are people whom we expect to come into existence and whose interests will therefore enter into our decision making. For example, if I have one child and expect to have another one soon, I would consider the second child’s interests as well as the first one when thinking about how much money I need to save for my children.

In the context of abortion, the “potential human being” is the foetus, whose interests do not necessarily enter into the decision, because his future existence is not expected and is, indeed, at issue. As BDL suggests, there are some tricky issues here for utilitarians about eg. whether such “potential human beings” have interests at all, and if so, whether they have an interest in existing, even if that existence will be miserable. These issues are not specific to abortion, as they are also raised by any decision about whether or not to bring a child into existence. However, they are very different issues to those raised by Stern and don’t really have anything to do with the pure rate of time preference.

So the two problems really are completely different. I think the only situation in which the second might bear on Stern would be if Stern were considering the possibility of global warming reducing the population and were wondering how to weigh the interests of those who might never come into existence as a result of it (as opposed to those killed as a result of it, who would obviously be harmed.) I don’t think this is a question he addresses (or needs to address, because it is not a scenario we can countenance.)

25

Paul 01.09.07 at 10:26 pm

Engels, I broadly agree with your analysis of the distinction between potential humans who will exist and those whose existence is at question. That’s the basis on which I’d exclude potentially aborted foetuses from the utilitarian calculus. But I think you actually need to make that argument, and be willing to defend it. It certainly doesn’t follow automatically or axiomatically that the unborn(yet) are morally different from the unborn(maybe)- you have to actually justify the distinction, which some people above do, and which JQ emphatically doesn’t. That’s my beef with his post.

I think you’re wrong if you’re suggesting that the relationship between discount rates (value placed on the potential members of future generations)and abortion (value placed on potential members of this generation) isn’t worth discussing, it seems clear that they’re related but (in my view nad yours) distinguishable issues. And, again, “that’s nothing to do with economics, you fool” failed to draw such a distinction.

26

John Quiggin 01.09.07 at 10:44 pm

Paul, as I said in the post, the points I would make if I was willing to go into this have already been made, very well, by others in the comments thread I point to. Engels also does a good job, as does conchis over at MR.

I don’t feel that I’m obliged to go into detail to explain why an irrelevant argument is in fact irrelevant when others have already done so.

27

Paul 01.09.07 at 11:07 pm

You do in fact quote a post from that thread though don’t you John? Just not any of the ones that make the argument on which you’d like to rely. That, to me, smacks of arguing in bad faith. I’d add that there’s a difference between issues which are distinguishable from each other and those which are mutually irrelevent. Engels’ argument gets you the first, but not the second, because nothing in his post explains the reason why the two different case ought, morally, to be treated differently. There’s no axiom at play here, just arguments. You’d have been better of making one of them.

28

Paul 01.10.07 at 12:06 am

In fact, here’s an extract from conchi’s post on MR, with which your original post secretly agreed:

“There’s a perfectly reasonable strand of thought on this that says we should treat non-existent individuals…as having no interest in existing”

That bang-on, I’d say, but the opening phrase falls along way short of claiming, let alone demonstrating, irrelevancy.

The link between these two issues is a perfectly askable question, and most of the actual rebuttals implicitly or explicitly agree.

29

Tom T. 01.10.07 at 12:08 am

It seems to me that another (and possibly more precise) way of illuminating this issue is to realize that fetal life, at whatever level of concern or rights one does or does not afford it, does not affect the discounting issue because it appears to an equal extent on both the present and the future sides of the equation. There are fetuses currently in being, gestating, and waiting to be born, and there will at any particular time in the future be future fetuses who are then gestating and waiting to be born. There doesn’t seem to me to be any reason why one would discount the value of future generations of fetuses at a rate any different than one would otherwise apply to generations of people already born.

30

Daniel 01.10.07 at 1:24 am

Paul, since a foetus is here right now and will turn into a person in a minimum of ten months unless action is taken, there is no sensible discount rate at all (and certainly no “market consistent” one) which will make it OK to abort that foetus if it wasn’t OK anyway. The problem doesn’t have anything specific to do with abortion and isn’t solved by making a different assumption about discount rates.

31

Daniel 01.10.07 at 1:24 am

Paul, since a foetus is here right now and will turn into a person in a minimum of ten months unless action is taken, there is no sensible discount rate at all (and certainly no “market consistent” one) which will make it OK to abort that foetus if it wasn’t OK anyway. The problem doesn’t have anything specific to do with abortion and isn’t solved by making a different assumption about discount rates.

32

Far Away 01.10.07 at 3:04 am

“In the year 2007 there will be 100 babies born if abortion were illegal, but only 80 if abortion were legal.” etc etc

To people who believe this argument, why not substitute contraception for abortion? Indeed, why not substitute masturbation (for men, anyway)?

At the end of this particularly slippery slope, I think that we reach the conclusion that every sperm is sacred.

33

uiop 01.10.07 at 4:45 am

Or, Paul, to put Engels and Daniel’s point more succinctly: there is not so much a “distinction” between the “potential” humans who will exist in hundred of years and the “potential” humans who are fetuses now, but rather a confusion between two uses of the the language associated with the word “potential.”

34

Paul 01.10.07 at 5:45 am

Daniel,
I think you’re trying to make the analogy between the two issue too literal. One argument for time preference is that we should treat individuals in the future differently, not because of any temporally based characteristics they might have, but because they are not real persons now and therefore do not deserve equal weight in any utilitarian calculus.

By arguing for a near zero rate of time preference you implicitly reject this argument, together with all other arguments one might make for lowering the moral value of future individuals.

Having rejected that argument, that not presently being alive reduces their moral significance, it is then reasonable to ask whether you would reach the same conclusion about all individuals who are not presently alive but may be at some point in the future. Whether we’re talking about 9 months or 100 years is completely, and I’d have thought obviously, beside the point. One can however reasonably (but not conclusively) respond that people who are only potentially alive can rightly be treated differently from people who are statistically certain to be alive. I buy that and JQ presciently supported Engels argument to that effect, but I suspect many people on the other side of thew abortion debate wouldn’t. That’s why you have the argument.

As I believe I’ve mentioned already, the gentleman JQ chose to quote appears neither interested in nor capable of engaging in that particular discussion.

35

Paul 01.10.07 at 5:52 am

uiop,
That’s fine, and obviously, as Daniel points out, there’s a distinction (or “confusion” if you think it does anything to clarify the point) between people who will be alive in 9 months and people who will be alive in 100 years.
From the point of view of this debate, what matters is if that difference is morally significant. Daniels, based on time, wasn’t. You’ve done no more than assert that yours is, and Engels, Conchi and apparently JQ have done the same (“There’s a perfectly reasonable strand of thought” you’ll recall). As it happens that asserted distinction makes sense to me, not least because of the consequences of holding the opposite view, as Brad Delong outlines above. But for you to argue “by asking for equal consideration to be given to these two classes you are confusing them” is a question begging argument; you’re assuming that the difference you’ve outlined in morally significant, and then helpfully provided the conclusion that, if it is, then they need to be treated differently. That’s not a substitute for demonstrating the reason why that difference matters any more than, say, timing.

36

John Quiggin 01.10.07 at 8:25 am

Paul, I’m not asserting that the difference is morally significant, just that whether it is or not has nothing (or almost nothing) to do with discounting. If you think abortion is wrong, changing the annual rate of time preference from 0 to 3 per cent is not going to make it OK, and vice versa. This point was made early on in one of the threads I pointed to.

37

engels 01.10.07 at 9:28 am

Paul – As far as I know, people don’t think abortion wrong because it harms a non-existent person in the future (by causing “him” never to have existed). They think it is wrong because it harms the foetus. (The fact that the foetus can develop into a person might be a reason for caring about the foetus but that is not at all the same thing as saying that that person is being harmed.)

And people haven’t just “asserted” that the two cases are different, they’ve tried to explain to you why they are. You seem to agree, so I’m not sure what kind of “demonstration” you still think is called for.

38

Paul 01.10.07 at 6:53 pm

John,
It’s clear that secretly agreeing with a variety of different people isn’t the clearest way to transmit your views – the relevance to abortion, which is clear to me, to the author of the original post and to Conchi, with whom you agree, is that, if one adopts a near zero rate of time preference that is inconsistent with viewing the interests of people not yet in existence as less morally considerable than our own. Given that approach the the interests of potential human beings, how then does one weight the interests of foetuses. This sounds, for some reason, eerily familiar.
Your “0 to 3 per cent” is precisely as relevant as Daniel’s “9 months or 100 years”, which is to say not at all. The point is not that people who propound low discount rates must hate abortion, it’s that there is a relationship between the moral questions that go to formulating each position. You can respond that you distinguish those questions, but not that they are completely unrelated.

39

Paul 01.10.07 at 7:03 pm

Engels,
That’s a bold summary of the anti-abortion movement, but even were it not it doesn’t resolve the underlying ethical question – why do you weigh the interests of my daughter who will be born to those of my son who might be born contingent on how you weigh his interests. That’s a stand alone question, and doesn’t rest on the vocal support of abortion’s critics, however intimately you’re familiar with their arguments.

“And people haven’t just “asserted” that the two cases are different, they’ve tried to explain to you why they are. You seem to agree, so I’m not sure what kind of “demonstration” you still think is called for.”
You’re confusing two issues here Engels. I’m perfectly clear on how aborted foetuses are different from future generations – in fact I can add to your reasons by citing Daniel, who kindly points out that foetuses are only 9 months away from (maybe) existing, and that Stern’s future generations are tens of years or more away. I could also add that they’re different because aborted foetuses will be primarily the children of first world nations, while Stern’s future generations will existy disproportionately in the third world. All of these are clear differences between the two classes, but the second two are clearly morally irrelevant. The distinction you draw, which is similarly clear, may or may not be morally relevant, but one certainly wouldn’t be able to draw any conclusions either way from your post, which doesn’t address the issue. Hence “assertion”.

To recap, explaining that two things are different by some standard is not the same as demonstrating why they ought not to be treated alike.

40

engels 01.10.07 at 8:12 pm

the relevance to abortion, which is clear to me, to the author of the original post and to Conchi, with whom you agree, is that, if one adopts a near zero rate of time preference that is inconsistent with viewing the interests of people not yet in existence as less morally considerable than our own

No, Paul: I’ve just read through Conchis’ posts on the MR thread and he or she does not seem to think anything of the sort.

I’m not sure I completely understand everything else you say, so let me just try to make my point again.

As far as I am aware, the issue in abortion is not about weighing the wrong done to a pregnant woman against the wrong done to a person who may or may not exist in the future. It is about weighing the wrong done to the woman and the harm done to the foetus she is carrying.

Apparently, you reject this summary but you won’t explain what you think is wrong with it. I don’t think it is controversial or partisan. You seem to want to characterise the wrong done by an abortion not as a harm inflicted on the foetus but as a wrong inflicted on a future person, but this account does not appear to be sustainable, because after the abortion takes place that person will not exist and it does not seem to be possible for a non-existent person to be wronged.

Finally, I did misunderstand your claim about assertions made without argument. If I understand you now, you are saying that although I explained why the cases are different, I haven’t explained why this difference is of any moral significance. But it should be clear from the above that the difference comes down to the difference between people who exist or will exist and ‘people’ who do not and will never exist. I do not think the claim that non-existent ‘people’ can not be morally wronged needs to be defended here.

41

MQ 01.10.07 at 8:31 pm

John is right, the original Economist poster (sounds like a Megan McArdle special) is nutty, and so are her defenders on this thread. How we choose to discount what happens to an actually alive person in the future is completely logically unrelated to how we assess harm to a fetus. A fetus is not an actually alive person and will never be an actually alive person (when the actually alive person comes to be, the fetus will no longer exist). They are two totally different entities. There are causal linkages between them, but how we choose to morally assess those causal linkages has nothing to do with discounting.

McArdle basically puts her energies into trying to score rhetorical points off liberals, and she thinks she has found one here. But it’s rhetorical, and mists away under observation.

42

Paul 01.11.07 at 2:38 am

Engels,
My summary of Conchi’s argument isn’t intended to relate to abortion, and as such it seems to be a trivial restatement of what zero time preference means- people who will be alive at any point in the future have the same moral weighing as you or I. Now one can go on and distinguish certain kinds of people not yet in existence from this general propisition, as I believe you and Conchi ultimately do, all I’m doing is setting up the prima facie issue to which JQ ought to have responded.

Secondly, I don’t think you can respond to an ethical argumnent against abortion with “the issue in abortion is not about [x]” for any and all values of x. I hinted at this above when I said that a summary of others’ views, even an accurate one (and one that excludes the value of a potential human is pretty far from being that), isn’t relevant to a moral debate. To restate the (free-standing) argument, if we count the future utility of people not yet born in the utilitarian calculus then that utility ought to count against a decision to abort. As I’ve said, I think you adequately, though not conclusively respond to that problem, but not by telling me what you think the critics of abortion think about it.

“it does not seem to be possible for a [potentially] non-existent person to be wronged [even by the decision to make them non-existent]”
This, and what follows (which does accurately summarise my position, thanks) is the key to the argument. And no, you can’t just assert this as a fundamental truth. While I basically agree with that view, one could easily argue that actions which reduce future utility summations are wrong per se, you’d have to actually explain why a reduction in a person’s utility by not permitting them to come into existence is to be prefered to an (ex hypothesi) smaller reduction in the utility of someone who will exist (and “will” here only operates in some vague statistical sense, which makes your argument all the harder I’d have thought). Conchi predcates his/her argument on this distinction existing, and you initially ignore it and then assert it as a fundamental truth. I don’t think you’re wrong, but I think the person who asked the initial question asked one hard enough that it warranted a response. JQ gave a substandard one, which is how we got here.

43

Paul 01.11.07 at 2:40 am

Mq, I think you miss the point, or at least manage to evade it by splitting hairs. Rewrite your post, ignoring the fetus and dealing only with the harm to the potentially existing person themselves. See how it reads before submitting it.

44

engels 01.11.07 at 10:00 am

“it does not seem to be possible for a [potentially] non-existent person to be wronged [even by the decision to make them non-existent]”

Paul – After the abortion takes place and the foetus is dead, no person will exist in the future. Thus your editorial “[potentially]” confuses the meaning of what I said. I am saying that a non-existent person can not be wronged (yes, if you like, “even by the decision to make them non-existent”.) I haven’t asserted this as a “fundamental truth” but it is what I (and I think most people) believe, and I think it is clear why. If you disagree, and you think that it is possible to wrong ‘someone’ who does not exist by causing them not to exist, then you will face these issues not only over abortion, but over any decision not have children eg. a decision not to have sex. Therefore, in addition to being implausible, this argument is not in any way specific to abortion and so does not make a good argument against abortion.

Needless to say, none of this has diddly squat to do with discounting.

45

John Quiggin 01.11.07 at 6:50 pm

And conversely the central claim of the right-to-life group is that foetuses are (currently, not potentially) human beings with all the rights of other human beings. This has,as engels says, diddly squat to do with discounting.

I thought in posting, and still think, that this was needless to say, but you’ve complained at length about my not saying it, so now I’ve said it.

Comments on this entry are closed.