I’ve always found Foucault pretty hard going, as I intimated in yesterday’s post, though I think he’s a more interesting figure than his epigones. As it happens, he is the subject of not one but two biographies. The first is David Macey’s “The Lives of Michel Foucault”:http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/0679757929/junius-20 which is scholarly and fact-filled. The other is James Miller’s “The Passion of Michel Foucault”:http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/0674001575/junius-20 , and is a tremendous piece of writing which presents itself as a “narrative account of one man’s lifelong struggle to honor Nietzsche’s gnomic injunction, ‘to become what one is’.” I really can’t recommend Miller’s various books highly enough. As well as the Foucault volume he wrote a very readable study of Rousseau — “Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy”:http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/0872203379/junius-20 — and a highly entertaining history of rock music: “Flowers in the Dustbin”:http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/0684808730/junius-20 (also published as “Almost Grown”:http://www.amazon.co.uk/exec/obidos/ASIN/0099409925/junius-21 in the UK). Miller is currently editor of “Daedalus”:http://mitpress.mit.edu/daedalus .
{ 22 comments }
Philippe Lourier 08.26.04 at 4:02 pm
There’s also an earlier biography of Foucault by French journalist and gay activist Didier Eribon:
http://amazon.com/exec/obidos/tg/detail/-/0674572874/qid=1093532003/sr=1-3/ref=sr_1_3/002-8285059-0016818?v=glance&s=books
Here’s a lengthy review of Miller’s book by conservative Roger Kimball (The New Criterion):
http://www.newcriterion.com/archive/11/mar93/foucault.htm
B.Kerr 08.26.04 at 4:18 pm
Miller, in addition to writing good books, is an excellent teacher as well. He teaches at the Graduate Faculty of New School University, where he teaches poli sci and philosophy and runs the Liberal Studies department.
Phedre 08.26.04 at 4:25 pm
Philippe Lourier beat me to it. I prefer the Macey and the Eribon biographies to Miller’s. Perhaps I should go back and re-read Miller’s book. I was 22 when I read Miller’s book. While I could see the value of his style and direction, I thought he was gratuitously tawdry and sensational. I’ll admit that at that time I was completely enamoured by Foucault’s writings.
In the subsequent 10 years I have acquired some much-needed distance from Foucault, Deleuze and Lyotard. Now would be a good time to re-read Miller. While at it, I will check out the Rousseau book as well. Thanks.
catfish 08.26.04 at 4:56 pm
Reading the New Criterion Review of Miller’s biography that Mr. Lourier was a strange experience. The entire review seemed designed to play upon long established prejudices without really engaging any of Foucault’s ideas. I’m not sure what it’s conservative audience could gain from the review but a shallow confirmation of unexamined views. I’m not very familiar with New Criterion, but is that their usual style?
catfish 08.26.04 at 4:57 pm
Reading the New Criterion Review of Miller’s biography that Mr. Lourier was a strange experience. The entire review seemed designed to play upon long established prejudices without really engaging any of Foucault’s ideas. I’m not sure what it’s conservative audience could gain from the review but a shallow confirmation of unexamined views. I’m not very familiar with New Criterion, but is that their usual style?
catfish 08.26.04 at 4:57 pm
Reading the New Criterion Review of Miller’s biography that Mr. Lourier was a strange experience. The entire review seemed designed to play upon long established prejudices without really engaging any of Foucault’s ideas. I’m not sure what it’s conservative audience could gain from the review but a shallow confirmation of unexamined views. I’m not very familiar with New Criterion, but is that their usual style?
catfish 08.26.04 at 4:59 pm
sorry about the multiple posts
McGruff 08.26.04 at 5:45 pm
Miller is also the author of the classic history of the early New Left in the U.S., Democracy is in the Streets–a wonderful book. The fact that he turned from the SDS to Foucault (ending up, despite his own misgivings, rather sympahetic) might say something about the the history of the left after the sixties in the U.S.
Alex 08.26.04 at 7:04 pm
I definitely vote for the Eribon bio. Eribon was sort of the Louella Parsons of French intellectual life (now, perhaps, replaced by Francois Dosse?) His work on Foucault draws on a life time of familiarity with the French scene and tons of previous work on other intellectuals (Dumezil, e.g.) who played an important role in Foucault’s career. His follow up book, ‘Michel Foucault et ses contemporaines’ is also excellent (the bit on Foucault dining w/Habermas is very funny), although not available in English afaik. I’d definitely endorse Eribon over the other authors.
Doctor Slack 08.26.04 at 8:50 pm
I think it’s worth asking how relevant the biography genre is to engaging Foucault, who himself was pretty adamant about putting the focus on the ideas rather than on personalities (this being one of the sources of his contempt for psychoanalysis). I for one would rather see more people reading his work directly, since only about 3% of those who feel keen to comment on it seem to have gotten around to this. The Foucault Reader, an old collection from Pantheon (1984) is still indispensable for this purpose and a useful corrective to the great masses of silliness that are still flung around about Foucault (eg. that he was a “postmodern” thinker, that he was a “philosopher of discontinuity,” that he was “anti-Enlightenment” and so on).
I’ve always been a little puzzled by Foucault’s reputation as a difficult read. I can see it with other continental theorists, but Foucault has never struck me as being particularly unclear or as anything other than a rather methodical species of positivist. Maybe it’s because so many readers are coming to him through a fog of mumbo-jumbo about “postmodernism” or preconceptions about his “leftist” politics? It just really strikes me as odd.
john 08.26.04 at 9:24 pm
>Foucault has never struck me as >being particularly unclear or as >anything other than a rather >methodical species of positivist.
If I said that Nietzsche had never struck me as anything other than a rhetorically ornate specimen of British empiricism, I might have a point, but you’d probably expect me to elaborate.
McGruff 08.26.04 at 10:19 pm
“a rather methodical species of positivist”?
You’re kidding, right? Even Foucault’s greatest admirers don’t think of his genealogies as being very historically scrupulous. And to miss the more arcanely visionary aspects of his work you have to concentrate on a pretty narrow part of its spectrum. One of the nice features of Miller’s book, by the way, comes in how he shows that Foucault was in fact not all that “adamant about putting the focus on the ideas rather than on personalities.” Like just about everything else, he was maddeningly ambivalent and ambiguous on this issue.
Scott McArthur 08.26.04 at 10:48 pm
I looked at the New Criterion Review as well. Why are conservatives so fixated with personal behavior? The mocking was so repetitive and dominant. It sounded like some bitter square who can’t get his wife to give him a blow job, so he’ll make up for it by tearing a dead hedonist a new one. Pathetic.
Yeah, ok Foucault is not the second coming, fine. Does it therfore mean his ideas have no value? I think his ideas on coercion would be something that all political persuasions could find useful. His ideas on how a society establishes truth from falsehood is also pretty nifty.
I think what makes him so inconvenient for so many is that his ideas make believing in ideologies very difficult.
Doctor Slack 08.26.04 at 11:30 pm
Even Foucault’s greatest admirers don’t think of his genealogies as being very historically scrupulous.
Nor do I — by “methodical” I was referring to his prose style, not his research methodology. And I should hope it’s obvious that being wrong about certain things is not mutually exclusive with being a positivist.
If I said that Nietzsche had never struck me as anything other than a rhetorically ornate specimen of British empiricism, I might have a point, but you’d probably expect me to elaborate.
Actually, I don’t think that specific point would need much further elaboration (and I happen to agree with it), but I see what you’re getting at. As it happens, Paul Veyne makes the point at length in the admittedly somewhat fawningly-titled but still very perceptive article “Foucault Revolutionizes History,” which can be found in the 1996 collection Foucault and his Interlocutors.
McGruff 08.27.04 at 2:26 am
Being wrong about certain things isn’t inconsistent with being a positivist. Telling wildly speculative stories (the ship of fools plied actual waters?) probably is. Foucault may have been an anti-metaphysician (with nevertheless a strong taste for the spiritual, evident among other places in his enthusiasm for the Iranian revolution as an apocalyptic event), but he was no methodical positvist, either in his style of research or his style of writing. You couldn’t read The Order of Things, I think, and believe that was so.
Timothy Burke 08.27.04 at 3:35 am
I second McGruff’s comments. Of all the things one might legitimately say Foucault was (and I do not think it is silly or misinformed, even based on The Foucault Reader, my copy of which is thoroughly dog-eared, to say he was “anti-Enlightenment”), of all the things, you can’t possibly call him a “methodical positivist”. Both halves of that characterization are wrong no matter how you slice it.
I don’t find Foucault all that difficult to read compared to many of the canonical figures in critical theory. But I think one reason he is perceived as difficult is that he had a lifelong habit (very much on display in the aforementioned Foucault Reader) of contradictorily abjuring or repudiating common interpretations of his work. If you chart out all those statements, they often cancel each other out, leaving it not at all clear what he meant to say, leaving it possible that he did not mean, for very deliberate reasons, to be “clear” in the sense of provisioning a useful foundational body of theory.
One thing that makes Foucault so attractive, however, is the clear sense of engagement that runs through all of his work. He was a social critic, without a doubt; his work often gives the sense that he is exposing or revealing something hidden, shameful, suppressed, even when he goes to considerable lengths (as in The History of Sexuality) to reject the entire idea of an emancipatory or liberating project.
Alex 08.27.04 at 5:18 am
Foucault was conflicted about examining the biography of an author. On the one hand he wrote an entire essay dissing the idea of biography-centric criticism (“What is an author”). On the other hand it was not at all unusual to do close readings of one author (“Herculine Barbarin” and “Raymond Roussel”). His own personality veered between a deep craving for publicity (his willingness to embrace the label ‘structuralism’) and a deep sense of privacy (not allowing any of his unpublished work to appear posthumously). This fear of being unable to fulfill the expectations other have of him (flunking his aggregation the first time around, e.g.) and his own workaholic drive to succeed are clearly part of a personality that was deeply ambivalent about how driven it was to success and how much scrutiny he himself cared to receive. This also explains other things, including his famous ticklishness about his work, and how he constantly revised it (consider the versions of ‘Maladie mentale et personalite’), or simply shifted focus (from an account of epistemes in Order of Things to an account of ‘subjectivization’ in later writings). For instance, he didn’t mind popular attention but often felt burned when he lost control of his ability to ‘spin’ his image — he was happy to be labeled a ‘structuralist’ at first, but later repudiated it after, as it were, he realized what signing to a major label entailed.
I don’t think there’s anything wrong in pondering someone’s biography, but I think the anglophone exoticization of Foucault’s life (suicide attempts! Leather!) doesn’t do him nearly enough justice, or get one very far in appreciating what French intellectual life was like before the education reforms. I definitely wouldn’t call him ‘spiritual’ or ‘apocalyptic’. His enthusiasm for the Iranian revolution was part of a widespread enthusiasm for popular revolt against American imperialism that was widespread that was common among the left at the time. Finally: Hard to read? Foucault writes wonderfully — even when translated into English! But I’ll admit that he comes out of a French tradition whose use of ‘evidence’ and ‘facts’ is often mindboggling to the anglophone. I think we forget at times that Foucault’s biggest influences as a student were Binswanger, Canguillhem, and Hyppolite — none of whom were exactly quantitative social scientists! Like many French thinkers, Foucault’s value to the English speaking world lies less in his specific findings (how this particular Italian city state conceived of the census) than a mood or outlook which proves fruitful once domesticated within our own paradigms.
McGruff 08.27.04 at 6:12 pm
Responding to the Iranian Revolution, Foucault made a strong effort to disntguish between the Marxian theory and practice of revolution–which he disliked for the way it “constituted a gigantic effort to demosticate revolts within a rational and controllable history”–and what he called by contrast “the enigma of revolts.” To wit:
“The enigma of revolts. For anyone who did not look for the ‘underlying reasons’ for the movement in Iran but was attentive to way in which it was experienced, for anyone who tried to understand what was going on in the heads of these men and women when they were risking their lives, one thing was striking. They inscribed their humiliations, their hatred for the regime, and their resolve to overthrow it at the bounds of heaven and earth, in an envisioned history that was religious jut as much as it was political. . . . it was also a question of millennial sacrifices and promises.†All this, Foucault adds, is reminiscent of “old dreams that the West had known in times past, when people attempted to inscribe the figures of spirituality on political ground.â€
I think it’s pretty clear from this and other writings that Foucault admired the Iranian revolution because, in addition to being a challenge to American imperialism, it did seem like an apocalyptic event. That seems a spiritual as much as a political interest to me.
Also, it’s true, Foucault does write wonderfully, but that doesn’t mean that he’s easy to read. Lucidity and beauty of expression are not inevitably the same thing and in the case of a writer who was often interested in being evasive or difficult, I’d suggest, could quite naturally pull in different directions.
Finally, since this thread began as a discussion of James Miller, it’s really quite unfair to suggest he exoticized Foucault’s life. It’s hard to imagine a book that makes a greater effort to be thoughtful and generous.
Doctor Slack 08.27.04 at 7:38 pm
McGruff: Funny, I don’t know of any species of positivism that disallows speculation. AFAIK positivism was conceived as a means of criticizing claims to transcendent knowledge; it has never been proof against false claims about historical events or any other subject, of which Foucault has been (quite rightly, IMO) accused. If Foucault had claimed that his knowledge of the Ship of Fools derived from some supernatural source or divine order, your objection would seem more relevant to me.
One of the reasons Foucault’s historical writing remains of interest, however, is that the contention underlying it (which boils down to “history should be the study of specifics rather than overarching teleological themes”) is fundamentally positivist. For me, anyway, this is the basic reason he remains relevant.
As for his having a methodical prose style, I really don’t see how this is such a shocking thing to say. One may not agree with the chains of logic he puts together — I find Madness and Civilization especially weak in this regard — but they’re certainly there.
As for the Iranian revolution, you seem to be reading far more into the quote you provide than is necessarily there. (People often seem pissed at Foucault for not sharing their polemical inclinations.) That paragraph doesn’t look much different to me from Foucault’s various writings on medieval spirituality and power relations, which he certainly showed no signs of “admiring.”
Timothy Burke: I think the way you characterize the attractions of Foucault’s social criticism is very perceptive.
Maybe you could elaborate on the “contradictorily abjuring” part, though. Since so many of the “common interpretations” of his work usually seem to me to stem from aggressive misreadings and selective distortions (e.g. the common trope that in talking about the connection of “power” and “knowledge” Foucault must be equating rationality with oppression and thus be “anti-rationalist,” just to take one example), I don’t see how he could avoid abjuring them. I’m admittedly not so much in the habit of reading Foucault-on-the-polemics-about-Foucault, though, so it’s possible there are instances of his contradicting himself that I’m not aware of.
I’ll leave Foucault-as-“anti-Enlightenment” for another day, except to say that I think it fundamentally impossible to be “anti-Enlightenment” if one’s epistemological concerns fit comfortably with, extend and/or supplement the spirit of rational inquiry that sets the Enlightenment apart as a tradition. (I’d go so far as to say even Lyotard, who was always reliable for a rant against “science,” isn’t truly “anti-Enlightenment” despite his apparent claims to the contrary.)
McGruff 08.27.04 at 8:15 pm
My point again isn’t that Foucualt made false claims, or even that he was speculative. It’s that he was more interested in telling provocative stories than in the difference between true and false claims–nor did his thinking leave him much ground for thinking the difference mattered. If he was a methodical positivist, he’d care a lot about evidence, wouldn’t he? He didn’t.
I think you’re wrong, too, Dr. Slack about my reading of Foucault’s reading of the Iranian revolution. And, though I find it an unattractive view, I’m not pissed off at Foucault for having it. The point of that passage, I think, is not just that the Iranians politicized religion, but that the event–like May ’68–was an enigmatic, non-rationalizable experience that transcended merely mundane political concerns. I suspect that it was for similar reasons that the Iranian revolution appealed more to him than other examples of resistance to American imperialism. But then, I also think that, in fact, he was ambivalent about medieval spirituality.
It’s an appealing view to say that Foucault “boils down to ‘history should be the study of specifics rather than overarching teleological themes'” (is that a quote?) but I don’t think it really fits the books Foucault wrote or the whole range of his concerns. It’s hard to conceive of how an “episteme” could be a specific, rather than an overarching theme–or how say, “panopticism” could be. I’m not saying those aren’t ineresting stories, but they don’t look like methodical postivism to me.
I’m not sure how positivism makes Foucault relevant either. After all, you could get that from plenty of sources. Foucault was exciting for other reasons, and I think Timory Burke is right that being anti-enlightenment is a good part of it. Why else would Madness and Civilization or Discipline and Punish be important? Granted there might be something fundamentally impossible about the stance, but it wasn’t like foucault to worry too much over that kind of thing.
Doctor Slack 08.27.04 at 9:30 pm
It’s that he was more interested in telling provocative stories than in the difference between true and false claims—nor did his thinking leave him much ground for thinking the difference mattered.
I don’t see any grounds to conclude that Foucault “didn’t care about evidence” or the difference between true and false claims from the fact that he was sometimes mistaken, overzealous or sloppy. On a basic level, it’s not like sloppiness or overzealousness is unheard of among historians who nevertheless regard themselves as meticulous in their approach to the evidence. Again, you seem to be confusing “positivist” with “accurate” or “careful;” a writer can be one without, sometimes, being the other.
I’m especially not buying that Foucault didn’t care about facts given that the main jist of his historical writing was the refutation of what he thought of as false claims (especially about historical themes like “progress”) through teasing out the specific and often very-minute details of a period. Trying to ascribe Foucault’s mistakes or build his occasional ad hoc rationalizations of them into some kind of grand philosophical disengagement from the whole idea of truth claims just doesn’t seem consistent with the bulk of his work.
It’s hard to conceive of how an “episteme” could be a specific, rather than an overarching theme—or how say, “panopticism” could be.
Ehhh, I rather thought the whole idea of the “episteme” was that it was supposed to be a direct engagement with how the people of a specific period constructed and viewed their society, resting on the particulars of their discourse and the power relations implied thereby. This was supposed to be in opposition to traditional overarching themes and categories of history, which Foucault persistently claimed were being adopted more or less as articles of faith without regard to the specifics of the evidence. (He goes on about this at length in Archaeology of Knowledge if I’m remembering it aright; it’s the contrast that was later bowdlerized into “discontinuity vs. continuity” by pop commentators and “postmodernism” enthusiasts.)
So yeah, the “episteme” as Foucault conceives it seems pretty unmistakably positivist to me. In fact, it strongly echoes other historical projects more commonly thought of as positivist — Popper’s writings about the history of science come to mind (though Popper of course didn’t share the Nietzschean preoccupation with “power”). This is not to say that Foucault’s own assertions about history can’t be made relevant in ways other than the literal, but that’s not especially relevant either to what Foucault claimed to be doing or, more importantly IMO, to the specific influence of his project on actual practising historians.
I’m not saying those aren’t ineresting stories, but they don’t look like methodical postivism
BTW, I’ll say yet again that my original reference to “methodical” was to his prose style. If you’re really not comfortable using the word in that sense, and you appear not to be, I’m more than happy to drop the term entirely. Whatever floats your boat.
The point of that passage, I think, is not just that the Iranians politicized religion, but that the event—like May ‘68—was an enigmatic, non-rationalizable experience that transcended merely mundane political concerns.
Sorry, where exactly are you getting that it “transcended merely mundane political concerns” from that paragraph?
I mean, Foucault certainly seems to be saying that rationality as Westerners conceive it (or rather idealize it) was not operative at the time — and how radical a contention is that, really, to make about millenarian movements, of which Shiite fundamentalism manifestly is one? — but I don’t see where he’s making any comparison of this to “mundane political experience,” particularly since most of his writing effectively contended that there was no such thing, and indeed didn’t much trouble with distinguishing “political experience” from other forms of experience. Maybe he mentions this specifically elsewhere in that article?
mcgruff 08.28.04 at 2:54 am
You’re right, Dr. Slack. I’m not comfortable describing Foucault’ prose style as methodically positivist. First because I don’t think the notion makes sense. Can a prose style be positivist? Second, because I think it’s the wrong description. Foucault seems to me variously lucid, enigmatic, lyrical, obscure, and more. To describe his writing as methodical seems to me to narrow it beyond recognition.
I think likewise to call him a positivist historian is possible only if you narrow Foucault’s work to an unrecognizable thinness. (It’s hard for me to see “the refutation of what he thought of as false claims†as the “main jist†of his writing or that his work “boils down†to the claim that “history should be the study of specificsâ€; I don’t recall him saying that, and it seems to me a pretty narrow construal of his work.) Or, vice versa, if you so broaden the meaning of positivist as to strip it of much descriptive value. If positivist merely means that Foucault didn’t think his ideas came “from some supernatural source or divine order,†then there’ s not much to distinguish him from any other historian, or indeed from almost any modern intellectual. Who apart from believers and straw men aren’t positivists? Why would you need Foucault to represent such an attitude?
Saying that “the whole idea of the ‘episteme’ was that it was supposed to be a direct engagement with how the people of a specific period constructed and viewed their society†seems to me to be such a broadening of positivism. The point of the episteme, as I understood it, was that discovering it was not direct at all. No one in the Renaissance said, hey, I’m in the business of representing. Epistemes, I think, were rather supposed to be the unstated conditions of knowledge that historical actors depended on without being aware of their existence. I think (in what seems to me an anti-positivist line) Foucault said in The Archaeology of knowledge that his research at that point was aimed at discovering the horizon against which any individual datum is perceptible. There’s nothing direct about discovering a horizon that historical actors don’t know exists. (If I remember right, too, he begins that book by saying that discontinuity was exactly what he was interested in.)
If such a horizon is not an overarching, or underarching theme or category, I don’t know what would be. And it seems to me that the episteme—and, less dramatically, other Foucauldian concepts like panopticism—require no less taking on faith than the windiest form of historical explanation.
Where exactly did I get the idea that Foucault valued the Iranian revolution for the way it “transcended merely mundane political concernsâ€? Fair question. This way. Praising the Iranian revolution, Foucault went out of his way to contrast it to traditional leftist politics which he blamed for their effort “to domesticate revolts within a rational and controllable historyâ€â€”precisely the path, he then went on to suggest, that was being forged by Islamic theocrats. Elsewhere he suggests (amazingly, I think) that social security and the welfare state do the same thing. And, far from contending that there was no such thing as mundane political experience, Foucault sometimes said as much about parties and electoral politics—all of which he disdains, saying at one point (Power/Knowledge, I believe), perhaps we have come to the end of politics and at another point (in the Foucault reader) that what interests him is much more morals than politics, or, politics as ethics and that he has particularly wanted “to question politics.†Around the same time, he laments that the “spontaneous†movement in which he had put his hopes had been a disappointment.
Through all these cases, I think, there’s a fairly clear pattern: ordinary politics (whether of the revolutionary left, of Islamic theocracy, or of representative democracy) are so administered, rationalized, and predictable as to be worthless. But sometimes there are spontaneous eruptions of resistance that make life worthwhile. These are inherently enigmatic and they recall a dream that once existed in the West. Add to that the fact that Foucault celebrated the Iranian revolutionaries, as he did those in Tunis and Paris, especially for the fact that they risked their lives, and it seems fair to me to say that he wasn’t just describing the Iranian moment as millenarian, he was praising the way its spiritual revolt amounted to an unusual and heroic politics absent from the rest of life.
Comments on this entry are closed.